|
|
Crisis,
Choice, and Change:
Some Tentative Conclusions
Gabriel A. Almond Robert J.Mundl
This book shows all of the marks of unfinished business, of work in progress.
The reader in searcli of hard theory, of hypotheses deduced from axioms
and subjected to rigorous tests of proof, will find little comfort in this
analytical framework and our collection of case studies. IE anything, our
study demonstrates the high costs of moving prematurely and without the
benefit of theoretical imagination and liistorical knowledge into an imitation
of hard science. Thus each approach to developmental causation, carried
on by itself and offered as developmental theory, has only succeeded in
painting itself into a corner. On the other hand, when used in a larger
strategy of causal explanation and when adapted for these purposes, they
turn out to be essential components of
an explanatory effort.
We began with several intuitive insights. The decision to turn to historical
case studies, wliich common sense told us would have to be explained by
a good theory of development, was intuitive. Having made tilis decision,
we gave up any prospects of coming out with a good research design- We began
witli a set of liistorical episodes, chosen because they were interesting
and important, not because they represented a systematic typology of developmental
causation. We lacked the theory to enable us to do that at the outset. We
proceeded step by step to apply tlie principal approaches to developmental
causation to these cases.
As we applied system-iunctionalism to the be fore-and -after phases of our
episodes, we discovered that the notion of a developmental curve, beginning
witli equilibrium, moving to disequilibrium, and then returning to equilibrium,
simply was not to be encountered in reality. We repeatedly found that the
polemic between Dahrendorf and Parsons had
to be resolved in .1 compromise
between the two positions. Even the most stable kinds of political situations
contained conflicting tendencies and potentialities. Thus we liad to describe
our before-and-after situation by using recurrent interactions and processes
that tended to maintain tlic system, and ttie connictual tendencies and
potentialities tliat gave us insight into possible directions of systemic
change and adaptation. Similarly, in the postcrisis stage in our case
studies-even though the level and heat of the crisis had subsided-we have
also to indicate tlie con-flictual tendencies and potentialities that
poiniecl toward future crises.
When it came to applying social mobilization theory in our case studies
it immediately became apparent tliai we had to complicate this way of
treating the impact of the environment on the political system in several
ways. We bad to distinguish between domestic and international environmental
impacts on politics. We also bad to distinguish between security or military
and economic impingement from the international environment, as well as
sucli political-psychological occurrences as "demonstration effect."
.Similarly, we had to distinguish between long- and short-term impingements,
as some of our case studies demonstrated that long-term social changes
might accumulate without significantly affecting levels of political demand.
Short-term fluctuations seemed to be the immediate triggers for political
crises, whether military or economic. It was necessary to complicate this
environment-system interaction analysis by pointing out that environmental
fluctuations can work both ways, that is, precipitate crises or allay
them. Thus we assimilated social mobilization theory as developed in that
body of literature to a much more complex set of theoretical variables
that separated environments, discriminated long-term from short-term impingements,
and lield open the
question of the direction of environmental impacts, i.e., crisis-inducing
or crisis-reducing.
In applying coalition theory to tlie analysis of internal political changes
and adjustments, we confronted tlie problem of turning a formal and simple
model into an analytic scheme that could effectively be applied to historical
reality. Tlie problem of loosening up coalition theory, separating its
elements into actors, resources, and issues, and developing ways of measuring
resources and issue distances turned out to be tlie most intellectually
challenging undertaking of tlie whole research program. When we had finally
worked these problems out at least to our partial satisfaction we discovered
that this did not enable us to explain the coalition and policy outcome,
but only to generate the set of logically possible coalitions from given
sets of actors, resources, and issues, and to rank them according to tlieir
resources, cohesion, ;ind policy propensities. To predict tlie winning
coalition we liad 10 turn to leadership and decision phenomena, as well
a.s 10 chiiiice.
When we finally confronted ilic leadership variable as an approach to
developmental causation we derided that we could only deal impres-sionisiically
with it. The reader will therefore observe that leadership phenomena tend
to be treated residually in our case studies. We decided that dealing
with leadership more systematically would call for another major research
undertaking. Thus we placed this issue on our agenda for future research
and make no claims of having done anything more than to specify ways in
which one could handle the leadership variable in such a way as to link
it systematically with tlie other three approaches to developmental causation.
However leadership phenomena clearly manifest themselves in developmental
processes both individually and collectively, and positively and negatively.
Thus our overall strategy of research might be best described as one of
trial and error, and what we are offering ow readers in this book is an
opportunity to share in this exploratory process.
We offer three sets of tentative conclusions in this final chapter. The
first is a cross-case-study analysis of the causal constellations and
sequences which our particular set of case studies manifests. Second our
case studies all in some way suggest explanations for differing patterns
of modernization and democratization. Third, and perhaps most important,
this experience takes us a substantial way forward in showing us how to
draw systematically from historic experience in generating better theories
of tlie causes and conditions of political stability and change.
CAUSAL CONSTELLATIONS IN OUR CASE STUDIES
Eacli study we have presented manifests a different constellation of causal
components. Eacli case study, however, assesses the value of these causal
components even wlien it approaches zero, when its absence may be a part
of die explanation of tlie outcome. Thus it is possible in our conclusion
to compare causal constellations across all our case studies.
STRUCTURAL-FUNCTIONALISM AND CAUSATION
For each case presented, we can characterize the antecedent system in
terms of its system-maintenance and crisis propensities, its "stabilities"
and "instabilities." In all tliese cases the preexistent system
includes structural or cultural features rendering aspects of it unacceptable
to one or another of tlie contenders, which enables us to identify a potential
for crisis, in tlie event of an increase in distance on issues or a wider
distribution of political resources. This, it now seems obvious, is universal
in political systems. There are no "final solutions," only more
or less stable adjustments to more or less stable environments. Challenge
is inevitable, and we liave only to locale (lie weak points that wilt
be tlie first objects of attack. But in some cases, tlie preexisting system
manifested little evidence of overt cliallcnge to tlie authority structure.
It required
substantial environmental pressures to shake up tlie system. In other
cases tlie conditions of crisis were obviously present in the preexisting
situation, as was evidence of political mobilization against the ruling
xoalition on certain issues. Rut tlie-crisis was rontnined, eitlier through
-- the effect of some highly salient "valence" issue (e.g.,
threat in tlie international environment), or by tcni|X)rarily effective
measures of repression or accommodation.
Our range of cases includes examples of tlie successful resolution of
difficult problems below tlie crisis level - whether that level is defined
in terms of our quantitative measures or by the criterion of whether or
not the "constitution" itself became an issue. Britain in 1832,
and especially in 1931, resolved serious questions below tlie crisis level
as we have defined it. as did Mexico and India. Specific manifestations
of structural and cultural features lhat were to affect tlie system's
capability for non-crisis response to tlie substantive issues that became
salient in each case examined Iiere are sliown in Table X.I.
In Table X.I we have ordered our cases according to tlie polarization
index, that is, tlie degree of crisis as measured by our authors on the
scale described in Chapter II. A score of 1 to 2 was an estimate of stability;
a score of 2 to 3 estimated manageable within-system conflicts; a score
of 3 to 4, crisis and confrontation; and 4 to 5, violence and revolution-
Tlie range of difference here is quite substantial-from one extreme of
tlie scale for France after the defeat in the war of 1870 and during tlie
Paris Commune, to tlie other extreme for India.
Tile two cases highest in polarization - France of 1871 and Germany of
1920- were lowest in the estimate of political system legitimacy before
the crisis, and were most dependent on effective system performance, taking
tlie form of some combination of accommodation, distribution of welfare
benefits, and repression of dissent (see columns 1 and 5, Table IX.1).
Tlie countries lowest in (lie polari/aiion index (e.g., Britain in 1931
and India) were higher in tlie estimate of system legitimacy- The four
cases in between are both at midpoint in the polarization index and in
tlie extent of system legitimacy.
When we discuss the developmental outcomes in our cases later in this
chapter it will he apparent that tlie liiglier (lie legitimacy of the
preexisting system, tlie more limited was tlie extent of structural and
cultural change in [lie outcome. Thus India and Britain (1931) came out
of their crises with only moderate changes in political structure. Mexico
and Britain (1832) weathered tlieir crises through changes in electoral
arrangements, |X)litical reorganization, and changes in public policy.
In both Japanese cases the constitutional order changed, and in the German
and French cases llie changes were revolutionary, i
TIlis first comparison across our cases allows us to distinguish two
models of political development: first, tlic gradual, limited, and perhaps
"insiifUcient" response o[ luglily legitimate systems; and seconil,
the more extreme adjustments characteristic of systems relying more heavily
on short-term effectiveness of performance.
Table X.I also indicates that the ".simultaneity" or "cumulativeness
of crisis" hypothesis, which holds tlial the number of salient issue
areas and (lie severity of ilie crisis are related (Almond and Powell,
1966:315 ft.), does not liold up well on tlie basis of our case studies.
The third column of Table X.I suggests a more complex pattern. India,
lowest on the polarization index, lias a twofold crisis of nation-building
(language crisis) and welfare, but the issues were separated sliglitly
in time and were cross-cutting rather llian cumulative. Mexico had a threefold
crisis of welfare, participation, and nation building. However, the salience
of these tliree issue areas was relatively low on the eve of the Cardenas
era. Germany and France had multiple crises, they tended to be salient
issues, and they tended to be cumulative rather than cross-cutting. Before
the Meiji crisis Japan had only a state-building (centralization-bureaucrati-zation)
problem, but it readied a higlier point in polarization than Mexico with
three issue areas. The Japanese issue of state-building, however, constituted
a tar greater threat to the structure of the Tokugawa constitution, whereas
Mexico cannot really be said to have been confronted by a systemic crisis
during the Calles era, though she was troubled by multiple issues.
Severity of crisis, therefore, seems to be explained by some combination
of salience, multiplicity, and cumulativeness of issues, so tliat the
same political elites and support groups are polari/ed on one highly salient
issue or combination of issues. Tlie key is salience and intensity of
antagonism, rather than number of issues. Multiple issues can accentuate
polarization or reduce it, depending on tlieir incidence,
ENVIRONMENTAL FLUCTUATIONS AND DEVELOPMENTAL CAUSATION
Jn Table X.2 we compare tlie environmental impacts that occurred in our
historical case studies. The numbers in tlie cells, ranging from 0 to
3, are judgmental estimates of magnitude of tlie impact of external pressures
on tlie stability of the system. Tlie sign tells us whether the impact
is stabilizing (+) or destabilizing (-). Tlie columns broadly divide these
impacts by environment (international and domestic) and type of impact
(military, economic, demonstration effect, social mobilization). Thus
in a very summary way we can differentiate among our cases according to
tlie magnitude and composition of tlie environmental aspects of causation.
But before examining tlie individual cases reported in the rows of Table
X.2, the columns indicate something about tlie different ways
environmental change can enter into developmental causal sequences. By
far the largest numbers are in tlie international military column, suggesting
that at least in lliese cases war or threat of war lias been [lie most
important political system destabilizer or stabiliser. Tlie first column
of Table X.2 shows some of the various ways this military variable can
affect stability. Thus. in Britain in 1832. a decline in military threat
after tlie Napoleonic wars unsettled the British polity. In France and
Germany, it was catastrophic military defeat; in tlie Meiji restoration
it was tlie threat of invasion and colonization by the Western powers
that triggered revolutionary change. In Japan in 1930-36 it was llie opportunity
for expansion in China tliat united (lie Japanese behind militaristic
goals, contributing to the fall of parly government but stabilizing the
polity under military control. In India in tlie 1960's tlie military threat
of China and Pakistan reduced internal cleavages in Indian politics.
Thus the interchanges between tlie international security environment
and political systems would seem to liave been the most powerful exogenous
variable in explaining system stability and change. The international
economic environment enters into tlie picture only in tlie British crisis
of tlie 1930's, when a generally deteriorating international trade situation
peaked into a severe balance of payments crisis, and in the Indian case,
when tlie reduction of foreign aid intensified famine risks but pressed
politicians toward a new production policy; and indirectly in the second
Japanese case, when the collapse in foreign trade set off a depression.
Tlie third column, international demonstration effects, has four entries:
(1) in tlie first British case, when tlie 1830 French revolution had a
mobilizing impact on Britisli opinion; (2) in Germany in 1918, wlien the
bolshevik revolution contributed to the polarization of German politics;
(3) in mid-nineteenth century Japan, when tlie invasion and colonization
of China dramatized tlie foreign tlireat; (4) and in Japan in tlie 1930's,
when tlie international trend toward military and totalitarian regimes
seemed to suggest an effective answer to tlie country's problems.
On tlie domestic side almost all entries are negative, and all eight cases
contain declining economic performance components (depression, unemployment,
food shortages, and famine), wliereas only six of tlie eight contain negative
entries for social mobilization. The exceptions are the Mexican and Indian
cases. Nevertheless tlie social mobilization variables played a role in
tliese two crises as well. In tlie Mexican case tlie enormous social turbulence
of the earlier pliases of llie Mexican revolution had created expectations
and attitudes among Mexican peasants and workers that Cardenas could mobili/e.
In India tlie relatively low level of social mobilization and the continued
liold of such traditional social structures as caste, village, and ethnic
groups gave tlie Indian elites a
deeree of bargaining freedom that enabled them to form ad hoc problem-solving
coalitions and thereby avoid liigli political polarization.
At least for these cases, ttie international security variable and the
economic performance variable are clearly tlie environmental triggers
of crisis and system change. They may also act cumulatively to accentuate
crisis or, at counter purpose, as simultaneous polarizers and consensus
makers. The social mobilization variables are important transformers of
social structure and culture in (lie long run, but it takes sharp deterioration
in economic performance to convert these structural changes into political
crisis and political change. But these eight cases are hardly representative
in time or place. A study of crises elsewhere in Latin America, Africa,
and Asia would undoubtedly give us a different set of mixes of environmental
causation. We have shown various ways in which the international and domestic
environments can impinge on politics. The values of tlie individual variables
will vary from one area to the
next, from one time to tlie next.
In Table X.2 it is clear that some of our cases were heavily loaded by
their environments, others far less so. France, Germany, and Meiji Japan
stand out with catastrophic defeat or acute military threat compelling
system response. Both British episodes were depression cases, with social
mobilization and deteriorating terms o( trade as the long-run destabiliz-ers.
As military threat and invasion are inherently more disruptive of stability
than economic threat, it is not an exaggeration to say that the French
and German cases reHect a larger environmental destabilizai-ion than tlie
two British cases. It would therefore appear that Britain in 1832 and
1931 had higher system legitimacy to draw upon in crises, and was less
heavily loaded by international and domestic change than France and Germany
in tlieir crises where legitimacy was lower and environmental pressure
more acme. These differences in legitimacy and burden go far toward explaining
the incremental problem-solving pattern ot Britain and the revolutionary
outcomes in France and Germany.
In tlie Mexican case tlie low level of environmental destabilization is
striking- Here tlie explanation of tlie outcome lias to rest upon leadership
behavior and prcexistent issues and conflicts ratfier than environmental
destabilization. Tlie transformation of Mexican politics in tlie 1930's
was attributable predominately to leadership will and decision:
llie populistic, imaginative, and resolute behavior ot Cardenas in mobilizing
labor and tlie peasantry.
COALITION OPTIONS AND -SEQUENCES
Our analysis so far lias enabled us to explain crises and their outcomes
in terms of constraints, pressures, and opmriunities. in other words,
"necessary" conditions. Tims in England tlie conclusion ot the
Napo-
630 CMJI'J, Choice, anil
Change: Some Tentative Conclusions
Iconic wars deflated (lie international security issue and permitted the
reform issues lo surface. A depression mobili2ed new political resources
created by industrialization ;ind urbanization. With a new mix of resources
and salient issues (lie old ruling coalition lost its cohesion, and new
options became possible. We move from the necessary conditions of change
lo the sufficient ones, Iroin constraining conditions to clioice. To analyze
clioice we need options and decisions. Coalition analysis yields the options;
leadership and clioice analysis gives us llic decision.
Table X.3 charts the coalition sequences in our case studies. Each coalition
outcome in these sequences represents a "power-policy package"
put logctiier by the actors to solve the problems presented by tlie crisis.
The individual case studies show oilier coalition possibilities at each
decision point. Here we only review tlie historic patli of decision, relating
it to our earlier discussions of systemic and environmenial constraints,
projecting it forward to tlie crisis outcome and its consequences.
Tlie coalition sequence in nineteenth-century Britain follows a steady
course of cliange in coalition composition from right-center to center-left.
Tlie post-Napoleonic coalition of 1819 is a Tory government following
a policy of repressing demands for welfare and electoral reform. Tlie
1826 coalition adds tlie Whigs to this constellation thereby increasing
its resources, but reducing its cohesion. Tlie coalition of 1829 moves
one step left dropping tlie Tory "Ultras" and picking up the
Radicals. It generates tlie first reform- that o[ Catholic emancipation.
Almost the same coalition produces tlie Reform Act of 1832. Tlie crucial
clioice point was tlie one between 1826 and 1829. A conservative coalition
might have lield its ground, even lost some Whig support, and moved toward
a repressive policy and coercive governmental apparatus.
It was, in Powell's words, a "complex transition period (in which)
no single coalition is really dominant" (Chapter III). The coalition
analysis tor 1826 and 1829 produces a broad selection of possible outcomes
within tlie "preferred set," witli policy propensities ranging
[rom repression to reform. Wlial tlie coalition analysis does in relation
to our preceding discussion of structural, cultural, and environmental
causation is test (lie limits of their explanatory cowers. From (lie range
of coalition possibilities - and more important, from the variety of policy
propensities which that range ofteis-we are given tlie limits of tlie
determinacy of these environmental factors. Where tlie winning coalition
is llie only one included in tlie preferred set, we must conclude that
preconditions, whether in the pi-c'cxisling system or as a result of environmental
change, were sufficient predictors ol the trend of cliange. But in many
of our analyses, tliose preconditions merely created propensities for
change that could be counteracted by choice and leadership factors; and
in some cases, tlie preconditions left pivotal decision makers with radically
ditfcr-
Gabriei A. Almond and Robert
j. Mundt
enl alternatives, different
mixes of policy ami power that had roughly equal chances of success. To
belter explain this argument, it will be helpful to consider llie range
of coalition possibilities case by case.
The second British case illustrates an incremental shift to tlic right
with the MacDonald Labour faction joining (lie Liberals and Conservatives.
A Labour-Liberal coalition built around a public works program was possible
in 1930, however, which might have moved Britisli politics moderately
left a decade sooner tlian such a sliift actually occurred. The environment
liad created the conditions for a new coalition that did not emerge, an
outcome we must explain in terms of leadership characteristics.
Decision making could decisively affect the outcome in conditions of substantial
redistribution of resources, such as France experienced in 1870 and Germany
in 1918. In France, Conservatives and Moderate Republicans occupied the
center of llie ideological range. In 1871 they derived no particular advantage
from this fact. Resources were so distributed tliat the preferred set
of coalition outcomes included only (tie conservative-monarchist alliance
tliat actually formed. Tliere was, then, no room for choice. By 1876,
however, tlie repeated demonstrations in by-elections of Republican popular
supmrl had evened out tlie distribution of resources, and made the pivotal
position of tlie center group highly significant. Tlie Republicans then
could clioose between shaky control on their own, or greater stability
by sacrincing policy preferences tlirough an alliance with llie Conservatives;
as we liave seen, they chose the latter power-policy combination. Its
emergence depended on (lie agreement of tlie Conservatives, for whom the
decision to abandon erstwhile colleagues to (lie right was by no means
foregone.
Tlie German case, like the French, began with a national coalition that
broke up over war reverses; unlike tlie French case, defeat resulted in
the emergence of a moderate left government. Tlie dominant Social Democrats
in this coalition also faced a policy-power trade-oft: a shift to tlie
left based on reform of the bureaucracy and armed forces might liave given
the republic a belter start, by reducing the traditional, authoritarian,
and nationalist resources and increasing those of the democratic center
and socialist left. This would liave been a high-risk decision with some
undeterminable probability of civil war and Allied intervention. Ttie
actual Social Democratic choice, a move back toward the right with large
resources and high coalition dissonance produced the "pseudo-democratization"
of llie Weimar Republic, preserving tlie antidemocratic resources of llie
conservative and nationalist parties, tlie bureaucracy, and the military
officer corps.
Mexico in 1935 providc-s us the truly exceptional case in which the range
for clioicc suggested by our coalition analysis is narrowed to a
single outcome - which did not occurl Tlie "rational" outcome
at that time, based on considerations of resources and issue distances,
would liave been an alliance of Callistas with the revolutionary generals,
which would have required a coup against Cardenas. Coalition analysis
could not have predicted the strong policy preferences or leadership skills
of Cardenas, who chose, outside the preferred set of outcomes, to jettison
the Callistas, mobilize tlie urban workers and peasants, and tlien form
a cohesive and effective coalition consisting of tlie Cardenistas and
the radical labor and agrarian leaders, based on resources which he himself
had created. This outcome clearly cannot be explained except by a high
loading on the factor we liave yet to consider, leadership.
In the Japanese crisis of the 1860's, the Satsuma-Aizu coup in 1863 destroyed
the old reliable patterns of political behavior, leaving an extremely
fluid coalition in which resources were much more evenly distributed than
before. The Shogunate could have maintained a preeminence in three of
tlie tour most viable coalitions, but rejected all these options that
miglit have left them with at least half a loaf. The solution they chose-going
it alone-was outside the range of preferred coalitions, and was thus,
in effect, preordained to fail.
Flanagan's study of tlie interwar crisis in japan points up a longer range
clioice situation, in which the viability of emerging political parties
depended on the mobilization and organization of mass support. But party
leaders failed to shake off the effects of their traditional origins and,
by not developing an independent resource base, they were unable to move
toward a ministry responsible to the Diet, or to depolitize the military.
The shallow base and lack of popular roots of the party system made it
relatively easy tor tlie conservative bureaucratic and military elite
to push tlie parties aside and move, in 1932 and 1936, toward a military
integration of Japanese government and politics and an expansionist military
policy.
Tlie Indian study differs from the others presented liere in its emphasis
on explaining persistence under conditions of acute tension and distress-the
language crisis and the widespread crop failure and famine. Nation-building,
or nation-maintaining crises, focus our attention on the problem of avoiding
disintegration. The coalition-making situation, then, is one in whicli
there is always a possibility of increased fragmentation and immobilism.
Resolution of this fundamental challenge tends toward a coalition of the
whole; when that is not possible, then leaders must search for a functional
equivalent, as in the Indian pattern of disaggrega-tion of issues and
tlie deconcentration of decision sites. This was possible in India because
of tlie cohesion of tlie Congress party elite, which made possible this
mode of negotiation outside the formal governmental framework.
These examples li;ivc illustrated
the limits of coalition possibilities, the varying decree to which actors'
decisions in these crisis situations were determined by structural, cultural,
and environmental constraints. But it would be a mistake to see coalition
and clioice analysis as always on the receiving end of this causal relationship.
Although their effect on political change is not independent of those
constraints, it is equally important to examine tlie effect of coalition
and choice on subsequent outcomes.
In most of our crisis resolution cases, coalition activity shows a unidirectional
shift along the contender spectrum, in response to shifts in resources
and issue positions. The transition is either to an entirely new set of
"winners" (Meiji Japan), or else it is based on the use, by
tlie flank group toward which the shift lias taken place, of its pivotal
position to maintain its influence in tlie new outcome (tlie Conservatives
in France, the Tory Center in 1R32 Britain, MacDonald in 1931 Britain,
Cardenas in Mexico, the bureaucracy in Japan of the 1920's and 1930's).
But the ability of (lie political system to cope with subsequent challenges
or crises is related to this coalition outcome, and at least two cases-Germany
and France - show coalition-formation movement first in one direction,
then the oilier, as tlie resolution of one challenge changed issue distances
and resource distribution to allow a different (and not necessarily adequate)
response to tlie next challenge. In France, the repressive solution to
distribution and participation demands culminating in the defeat of tlie
Commune opened tlie door to a more limited accommodation of participation
and the definitive rejection of forms of legitimacy not ultimately based
on suffrage. In Germany, war, defeat, and related problems made possible
the emergence of a new resource distribution favoring the Social Democrats,
which presented tlie contenders with a new set of coalition considerations.
At this point, the Social Democrats opted for power over policy, reversing
the direction of coalition-formation movement, and attempted to stabilize
that movement at a point where they were unable to affect the environment
or. consequently, to cope with future crises.
We have paid considerable attention liere to choice as a trade-off between
power and policy and resources and issues. From the cases examined, we
might speculate on the implications of these trade-offs for political
change. It would appear that tlie greater the adjustment to be made in
the "constitution" hy a new coalition, tlie lower its ruling
potential is likely to be. Tlie more extreme tlie policy preferences of
tlie ruling coalition, the greater its polari/ation from other actors,
and tlie likelihood that oilier actors will not join or support the coalition.
Facing increased uncertainly ;tbout tlie consequences of pursuing its
innovative goals, tlie new elites are pressured 10 sacrifice innovation
for safety. Here tlie crucial variable i.s risk-taking. Thus llie German
Social Democrats,
faced with tlie clioice between a broad coalition to tlie right, or a
narrowly sufficient coalition to tlie left. cliose a low risk-taking strategy.
Cardenas's option was to proceed with tlie coalition tliat met his policy
goals, shoring up its originally high instability in a series of remarkable
maneuvers - in other words, a high risk-taking strategy. A more effective
response to tlie problems precipitating crisis came from a narrowly based
coalition tliat represented sharply denned policy responses. These two
examples suggest tlie hypothesis tliat tlie stability of a crisis outcome
may be directly related to the size of tlie emergent coalition in the
short run, but inversely related to it in tlie long run.
Tlie crucial factor, then, in tlie success of an innovative strategy is
the capacity to mobilize and create resources that may require a high
input of creative leadership as well as tlie availability of resources.
LEADERSHIP. COALITION SEQUENCES, AND OUTCOMES
Our coalition analysis alerts us to the power-policy options in given
crises. Tlie value of this analysis is tliat it forces us to specify all
of the logically possible coalitions, and order them by their resources
and cohesion, thus taking the logic of explanation one further step. It
tells us tliat the winning coalition should be in this set of coalitions,
and further tliat it will most likely be in a particular subset that includes
those coalitions with "reasonable probabilities" of forming
(i.e., the preferred set). The assumption is that freedom of choice is
limited to this preferred set.
In judging the strength of llie leadership variable we can employ tins
preferred set of options as a kind of measure or scale of tlie magnitude
and quality of leadership as a causal variable. It will tell us something
of the risk-taking propensities, tlie policy propensities, the strength
or resoluteness of leadership, and tlie skill properties of leadersliip.
Tlie most striking example of'leadership causation is tlie Mexican case.
Cardenas broke from his alliance with Calles, moving in early June 1935
from an immobilist coalition with more than lialf tlie resources to a
coalition with the left-labor and peasant leadersliip and the CediUistas.
The new grouping at that time controlled less tlian half tlie resources,
but supported the reforms tliat Cardenas favored. Within a month from
the formation of this coalition its share of resources had increased to
over half. Within a year Cardenas was able to drop the CediUistas, thus
forming a more unequivocally reformist coalition witli two-tliirds of
the resources. By 1938 lie liad shape<|I a powerful left-oriented coalition
dominating almost three-fourths of (lie resources. Thus we can say with
some confidence that a willingness to take risks, a resoluteness in policy
direction, and Cardena&'s skill in resource mobilization form a large
part of the explanation of [lie reformist outcome of tlie Mexican case.
Our best measure of C;ii"deiias's leadership ability i.s tfie fact
tliat his coalition clioice in late June 193f> was outside the preferred
set of outcomes; lie
had, in effect, used the uncertainties of real-world decision making to
his advantage, producing an outcome that would not have been possible
had all (lie actors possessed all the relevant information on that clioice
situation. In the case of Ramsay MacDonald we liave seen how, in 1931,
he missed the opportunity to form a Labour-Liberal coalition tliat was
the most attractive in the preferred set, at least in terms ot working
toward policy goals lie had long espoused.
Thus, the effectiveness of leadership must be judged relative to the decision-making
context in which it is exercised. To consider, first of all, the constraints
of the preexisting system, it seems that where political structures are
highly legitimate, individual roles within them tend to be precisely defined.
Sometimes, the cultural environment has a constraining effect that transcends
given structures or regimes; where, as in the Japanese cases again, value
is placed on consensual decisions at all levels of society, the ability
of an individual to strike out in new directions is clearly limited. Undoubtedly
some level of restraint of this type occurs in all societies, and in all
the cases considered here, effective leaders liad to break from the rules
of the game - an act that increases tensions independently of the issue
positions involved- Thus, Cardenas incurred the special onus of breaking
with leading members of the "revolutionary family" - an act
seen as a breacli of faitli that could only have added to the issue distances.
Just as the range of coalition options is enhanced by clianges that aggravate
potential crises in the preexisting system, so do such changes open new
possibilities for the contenders- Even the feudal Shogunate saw a wider
range of possible outcomes as a result of Perry's arrival. In the chaos
following military defeat in 1870 France and 1918 Germany, contenders
were led to consider a much wider range of alternatives than previously
would liave occurred to them. Indeed, an innovative leadership role occasionally
becomes an institutionalized part of political response patterns. The
"man on horseback" is a product of social and political confusion,
his chances of success inversely related to the viability of preexisting
structures as crisis tlireatens. Some political systems periodically make
room for such figures, as when in repeated crises the pattern develops
of resorting to a charismatic figure to reduce the polarization among
contenders when none of themlhas the resources to prevail. Sucli was the
case in nineteenth-century France, where a pattern of this type was set.
The redistribution of political resources following the defeat of the
Commune eliminated the need for a Caesaristic solution to the problems
faced by tlie Third Republic; but tlie tendency endured and was manifested
again throughout tlie Third, Fourth, and Fifth Republics.
The constraints of llicsc macro- variables on leadership are quite faith-
fully reflected in tlie clioice range specified in our coalition analysis.
Wlien issue distances are low and coalition patterns traditionally flexible,
many possible outcomes will be included in the preferred set. When long
practice and firmly established ideologies dictate ratiier rigidly which
coalition partners are appropriate, or when issue distances are extreme,
then even when environmental impact has brought about fundamental reassessments
and suggested new realignments, the preferred coalition list may be small
and the realistic options limited.
The quality of leadership must be measured against the scope of the leader's
discretion- Cardenas wrought dramatic changes in a situation where environmental
impact did little to create a "crisis," and where the solution
lie chose would not have been evident from the estimated resources available
to him at the time of his decision. MacDonald, on the otiier extreme,
acting in a period of high insecurity when new solutions were actively
being sought, failed to lake a lesser risk.
In Table X-4 we have rated leadership properties for each of the cases,
considering only the preeminent actors at crucial decision-making phases.
The cases are coded dichotomously by strength of leadership, by which
we mean a set of clioices by a leader or leaders which optimizes the power
base and tlie policy goals of a coalition. The table also indicates whether
leadership was exercised collectively or by an individual. Our distinction
here is between those interrelationships of high-placed individuals witliin
a given contending group tliat are symmetrical, and tliose that are asymmetrical.
Obviously, this distinction is somewhat arbitrary: in 1832 Britain, for
example, sucli figures as Grey were especially prominent. But Grey does
not compare with, say, Cardenas, in tilis respect, and the Reform Act
was actually a product of wider Whig bargaining to tlieir left and right.
The Radicals also showed skillful leadership in bringing mass discontents
to bear on tlie political process, but tlie Wliigs were equal to tliem,
benefiting from tlieir mass support in exchange for little immediate gain
for tliose supporters in terms of the conditions causing unrest. Britain
in 1931 was a contrasting case in both respects: political decision making
tended to be concentrated in a single leader, MacDonald, who, as we have
seen, made poor use of rather wide
scope for innovation.
The same can be said of the collective leadership oE the German Social
Democrats. As with oilier contenders whose policy propensities require
departures from tlie status quo, they can be faulted tor not taking the
risk of loss of control necessary to turn the corner. MacDonald's action
in June 1931 is even less excusable; lie cliose to hold onto a coalition
lliat was less effective than alliance with tlie Liberals would liave
been. In other words, his choice at that early point in the crisis increased
neither power nor policy. The German Imperial government and the military
reflected the weakness of conservative leadership after Bismarck in their
stubborn persistence with political forms and military ends that were
incompatible with their needs for wide support in a crisis period and
with their international situation. Theirs was an unrealistic choice of
conservative policy over power. The Social Democrats, as we have seen.
gnve up tlieir chances for policy change at a lime when the direction
of shift in political resource distribution suggested risk-taking.
In the Frencli case, leadership
was decisive in all the various outcomes. Napoleon III no longer showed
the decisiveness and resolve that his Caesaristic role required in (tie
last years of tlie Second Empire. Thiers' political skill and experience
in the struggle with the Communards, in contrast to their lack of direction
and misjudgment of tlieir resources. largely explains the shift in resources
in his favor in May 1871- His political skills in the formative period
of the Third Republic and his perceptive appraisal of resource values
explain his preference shift on the form-of-governmem issue. He put his
policy preference for societal stability over the short-run utility of
his own faction, in moving to the ultimately more effective coalition
based on republican institutions.
The Shogunate in the last days of Tokugawa Japan acted on political concepts
that had been deeply implanted in that long and stable period of feudalism.
Their strategy of going it alone in the early 1860-s on an insufficient
resource base was only possible because of the lack of information available
to oilier contenders. Once the information lag was overcome, the Shogunate-s
refusal to accept a wider coalition meant that in time coalition options
would appear that would exclude it- The Meiji regime's vigor and openness
10 new information made it a classic example of effective coping with
an initially threatening environment. The party leaders in Japan of the
1930-s never fully appreciated that a responsible parliamentary government
required an appropriate resource base in popular support. Rather, the
military-bureaucracy alliance developed that popular support once the
parties had missed their opportunities and
been thrust aside.
This sketching in of the leadership variable goes beyond the data base
of our program. Our judgments are impressionistic though they seem plausible
in the light of historical evidence. Though it leaves our work incomplete,
it may be appropriate to pause at tins point and give the choice and decision
aspect of developmental causation the kind of research and analytic effort
it deserves. We have developed systematic ways of establishing the constraints
and options in political situations and the ways in which tlieir outcomes
are determined: What ranges of freedom of choice there may have been in
historical contexts, or may be in contemporary situations, and how leadership
and clioice qualities may effect the exploitation of tliese opportunities,
are the problems of future research.
THEORETICAL AND METHODOLOGICAL IMPLICATIONS
Although the principal purpose of this book is exploratory, it provides
some demonstration of the advantages of this approacli to develop_ mental
causation over earlier attempts at historical developmental explanation.
Surely, Barrington Moore-s landmark study of alternative
routes to industrialization (1966) is one of tlie most im)K)i-tant of
tliese attempts. Yet it would appear to be substantially oversimplified
and over-determinist in the light of our examination of four cases that
are either included or treated in Ins comparative analysis - Britain and
France on one hand, and Germany and Japan on the other. Though lie qualifies
these hypotheses here and (here in Ins work, it is not an exaggeration
to impute the view to him tliat (lie democratic-capitalist route to modernization
had been substantially determined in Britain in tlie seventeenth century
with tlie commercialization of agriculture, and in France in the late
eighteenth and nineteenth centuries with the destruction of the aristocracy
and tlie emergence of an independent peasantry. Moore argues that tlie
German fascist-authoritarian route to industrial modernization was predetermined
by the fusion of royal bureaucracy and landed aristocracy in tlie seventeenth
and eighteenth centuries, and in Japan by tlie alliance of bureaucracy
and landliolders in the latter half of the nineteenth century. His effort
at a parsimonious social-structural explanation of tlie differences in
tlie patterns of political and economic development leads to a loss of
discrimination in his interpretation, and a sense of inevitable drift
once a course lias been set.
For example, if we illuminate the interplay between social structural
change and political change in Britain in tlie eighteenth and nineteenth
centuries it would appear that Moore lias overestimated the determinacy
of the British developmental pattern, Our 1832 case study suggests that
Britain in the 1820's had an option for a responsive "undemocratic"
solution to tlie destabilizalion of British politics resulting from industrialization
and tlie termination of the Napoleonic wars. Close examination ot this
episode suggests tliat from tlie perspective of this period in British
history the Whigs and tlie Tories might have moved either way-toward reform
or repression. Tlie memories of members of (tie political elite and their
risk-taking propensities provide us with tlie "sufficient" explanation
of tlie reform option.
Our three nineteenth-century European cases raise some rather serious
questions about Moore's interpretation of the causes of democratic and
fascist modernization. Tlie possible British option in the 1820's of a
center-right coalition in favor of repression might have turned the British
developmental path somewhat in the direction of tlie French and even German
pattern. And a France led by a more effective Napoleon III in 1870, or
by a more effective conservative-monarchist coalition in 1872, might have
come out with a constitutional monarchist solution and perhaps moved toward
a more British type of developmental patli. A Prussia, even with Bismarck
but without tlie Frcncli gift of tlie triumph of 1870, might have been
unable to produce a Second Reicli witli tlie particular mix of institutions
and classes that stood in the way of effective democrali/ation. Although
the m;i(To-variablcs or class structure give us a
part of the explanation,
it would seem that the micro-variables of coalition options and human
clioices had considerable independent causal
value.
Though Moore's treatment of German development is briefer, it seems
to be particularly oversimplified and overdeterministic. He not only seems
to have ruled out other options in the nineteenth century, he overlooks
the opportunities for choice that may still have existed in the twentieth.
If our case study is correct the left-center option in the 191&-1920
period might have reduced tlie conflict propensities of the Weimar
period and avoided National Socialism.
We feel a bit less confident in asserting that Japanese political development
liad another option during the rise of political parties in Japanese politics
during the first two decades of the twentieth century. The party elites
may have had a choice of consolidating a democratic party system through
the development of party organization and the legitimation of trade union
organization. This would have provided the resources that might have enabled
them to resist the pressure of the conservative forces of Japanese politics
and carry through a democratic integration of Japanese government and
politics rather than collapsing under an authoritarian traditional one.
Similarly, Moore's reductionist method conceals some fundamental differences
in the German and the Japanese developmental patterns. In the German case
industrialization and social mobilization were associated with the development
of mass party organization and the effective formation of interest groups.
Hence a populistic component had to be built into the authoritarian solution.
In Japan industrialization was not accompanied by significant political
mobilization and organization. Consequently, the Japanese solution was
more traditional and authoritarian, lacking tlie mass mobilized parly
that we usually associate with fascism.
Robert A. Dalil (1971) has also formulated a theoretical model of alternate
historical pathways, viewed from the probability that they will result
in stable democracy (or "polyarchy," the closest empirical approximation
ot the democratic ideal). Tlie value and limitations of the insights he
provides emerge rather clearly from an attempt to fit them to
the examples in our case studies.
Dalil suggests two dimensions along which to measure democrat! za-tion:
liberatiialion, or tlie legitimation of opposition and competition tor
authority positions; and mcltt'.ivcness, "tlie proportion oE tlie
population entitled to participate on a more or less equal plane in controlling
and contesting tlie conduct of government" (1971:4). Dahl identifies
tour logically possible combinations of extreme highs and lows on each
measure: (1) closed hegemony, witli neither competition nor wide participation;
(2) competitive oligarchy, wliere contestation is restricted to a small
elite; (3) inclusive hegemony, witli wide participation but little oppor-
tunity for public contest; and (oI) polyarchy, the combination of inclusive-ness
and competition. He then identifies three possible paths from hegemony
to polyarchy: direct inmsition, or through one of the two "intermediate"
paths (i.e., competitive oligarcliy to polyarchy or inclusive liegemony
to polyarchy).
A major difficulty with Dalil's approacli is its treatment of the demo-cratization
process in nondialectical terms. Tlius in's model suggests that stability
and democracy must he sought in a one- or two-stage sequence in which
liberalisation and inclusiveness must be ordered. His polyarchic solution
is to proceed first u'itli competition, providing for inclusiveness only
when a "gentlemen's agreement" on the terms of political competition
lias been firmly established.
It is perhaps unfortunate tliat in the development literature which deals
witli democratizaiion, the prerequisites of stability and of democracy
are not usually disaggregated for analytical purposes. To draw on one
of our cases, in France in 1875, all contenders accepted, if they did
not embrace, the legitimacy of electing office holders by mass suffrage.
This was a victory for llie champions of inclusiveness. But it was a victory
accorded after the range of allowable competition iiad been greatly reduced.
Under these conditions, Tliiers perceptively foresaw the place of mass
suffrage in [he Third Republic as a new means of providing symbolic support
to the authority structure, while having a minimal impact on policy. Once
the range of contestation had been reduced by suppressing the revolutionary
left, inclusiveness was much less salient as an issue, and was accepted.
Was this the achievement of stable polyarchy in France? Yes, in the short
run, for a mass electorate could choose among competing candidates. But.
a more thorough democratization developed only much later, when this inclusive
electorate was provided with a range of competing contenders that adequately
reflected the variety of political preferences seeking expression in France.
We would conclude from this analysis tliat, in the interplay of elite
clioice and mass political mobilization, it is necessary for stability
that contestation advance ahead of inclusiveness as Dahl suggests; but
we would add that it is necessary for democratization that inclusiveness
be established ahead of contestation. The paradox disappears over time,
as we have seen in the French case, in the dialectical development of
first one and then the oilier.
We can test these propositions witli our British cases. According to Dahl
(I971:3'l)> British development followed the path from closed liegemony
to com]^etitive oligarchy to poly;irchy. Our contention, however, based
on our two Brili'sli studies, and the historical events between them,
would be llial British development is more aptly characterized by a
zig-/ag path along die diagonal, i.e., llic path of direct transition
(Figure X-l). We liave seen that the earlier emergence of competition
led to movement toward inclusiveness in 1832. But this and succeeding
moves toward inclusiveness gave impetus in turn to wider competition.
The 1832 outcome was possible because the range of competition could be
restricted to Tories and Wliigs; the lfi67 suffrage extension could be
adopted because the competition could lie restricted to Conservatives
and Liberals. In the final extensions of suffrage in (lie twentieth century,
the Liberals were replaced by Labour, as a set of alternatives emerged
that more closely reflected the distribution of resources and issue positions.
Dahl's preference for the earlier emergence of competition fits the short-term
analysis of France in 1871; the high level of inclusiveness that had emerged
under Napoleonic hegemony could not sustain the sharp polarization of
that year. The level of competition fell, however, with the collapse of
the Commune, to a point tliat could support high inclusiveness. Witli
tlie principle of wide participation firmly established, the range of
competition inevitably increased giving substance to the democratic forms
toward the end of the century. However, those contenders who had been
included, then forced out of the arena in sharp development reverses along
the dimension of competition remained uncommitted to the rules of the
game, and created tlie condition of immobilism that marked tlie Third
Republic (Figure X.2).
In our German case, the missed opportunity of the Social Democrats in
1918-20 was to reduce competition to a level commensurate with the establishment
of a stable polyarchy - but in tills case by eliminating the resource
base of the riglit-wing contenders. The outcome was again an immobilism
deriving from the existence of contenders that were hostile to the Weimar
Republic. Dahl (1971:129) suggests an appropriate axiom:
>
"The greater tlie belief within a given country in the legitimacy
of the institutions of polyarcliy, tlie greater the chances for polyarchy";
but, as in Ins discussion of other conditions affecting the attainment
of stable polyarchy, he does not systematically connect subculture configurations
and elite belief systems to his elaboration of historical sequences.
It would appear that any significant movement along one dimension will
induce movement along the oilier; if a "vertical" movement is
in some way inhibited, pressure intensifies to slow or roll back movement
along tlie horizontal dimension as well, until an appropriate point of
equilibrium between tlie two is readied, as in France in May 1871 (Figure
X.2). Because tlie two dimensions of movement are associated with eacli
other, tlie most stable path of democratization will be along the path
of direct transition. As inclusiveness must be accorded in blocs (not
one voter at a time), a perfectly smooth curve cannot be attained. Hence
the zig-zag path along the diagonal may be the route to polyarcliy that
keeps competition and inclusiveness in sufficient balance to avoid crisis
and instability.
Dahl's elaboration is, in our view. restricted by his description of historical
patterns in terms of four ideal types, whereas an adequate explanation
requires measurement at intervening points. Here our use of the polarization
index in measuring competition and our quantification of the more important
varieties of |x>litical resources in measuring inclusiveness give us
a basis for moving along Dalil's dimensions with something like tlie precision
required.
These criticisms of tlie work of Moore and Dalil are not intended to detract
from their creative insigliis, but to suggest how we may get beyond the
limited explanatory power of their formulations. Tliese limits result
in the fust instance from a deterministic treatment of politics (plus
a failure to consider llic effect of iiilcrnation.it politics), and in
(lie scc-
ond from an ahistorical, nondialectic approach. We would argue that our
approach enables us to win back a bit of the autonomy of the political
sphere, rehabilitate tlie role of human choice and creativity in developmental
problem solving, and chart the outcome as a complex and continuous historical
pattern.
Furthermore, these critiques of Moore and Dahl are not to suggest that
the rest of us who have engaged in developmental theorizing have done
any better. They suggest the advantages o( a method tliat deals more effectively
with the interaction of politics and its environments and that illuminates
tlie relationship between constraint and choice in political problem solving.
We have learned in (.his study bow to do better research on comparative
political development. And it may be useful to spell this
out a bit more explicitly by way of conclusion.
The purpose of scientific work is to enhance our capacity to explain and
predict, and insofar as we succeed in doing this, to attain our own goals
more surety, more efficiently, more economically. Though some of us in
political science may view our problems with the disinterested curiosity
of a pliysicist, a discipline that deals with human conflict, coercion,
and welfare can hardly escape moral responsibility whether through the
mechanism of professional conscience, or through tlie expectations of
our constituencies and audiences. '
"We suggest that the approach illustrated in our case studies is
a more
effective way of gelling at explanation, prediction, and control of political
development than the approaches so tar employed or recommended in the
field. To begin with explanation, ttie model we use in our explanatory
efforts satisfies the requirements of a good model. Having reaped the
heuristic value of mechanical, biological, and cybernetic analogies, we
have dropped these analogies, and liave constructed a theoretical framework
appropriate for analyzing politics and political change- In developing
and testing the applicability of this model we have used a "most
different case study strategy of comparison" (Przeworski and Teune,
1970:33; Lijphan, 1971:687), a strategy that requires us to sample a wide
range of variation of the phenomena being investigated to determine whether
we have included all tlie important tlieoretical variables, and have some
understanding of their modes of interaction. The selection of cases in
this book illustrates tlie uses of this kind of exploratory strategy.
In future developmental research we will be better able to deal with such
variables as tlie impact of tlie international environment, or of leadership
on political development. Our understanding of tlie various ways these
and other variables may affect development has been greatly enhanced by
tlie dissimilarities of tlie cases we liave examined. It lias given us
more confidence that we liave a set of related concepts "able to
travel" in time
and space (Sartori, 1970:1034).
Having formulated and tested this analytical model on a wide range o(
cases, we suggest that we can now benefit from a "most similar comparative
strategy" (Pr/eworski and Tenne, lOPO:?!; Lijphart. 1971:688). Indeed,
as Lijphart argues, tlie strategy of comparison that comes closest to
the scientific ideal of experimental control is tlie comparison of [lie
same political system at adjoining points in lime. Our two British and
two Japanese cases demonstrate tlie advantages of a diachronic comparative
case study strategy, particularly the Japanese case studies that were
done "back to back" so to speak.
If we want to be taken seriously in our efforts to explain how Britain,
France, Germany, Italy, the Netherlands, Spain, and tlie like, got to
be the way they are (and our literature abounds in such propositions)
we shall have to move now to longitudinal studies of political development
tliat combine lime series analysis witii "crisis, choice, and change"
analysis. Tlie field seems generally to agree on tlie desirability of
longitudinal analysis of political development. Our work suggests that
a set of time series measuring environment and systemic change at the
macrolevel for any political system will leave tlie developmental path
unexplained unless the microlevel of coalition options and leader choices
are "factored in." Tims, as Rittberger (Chapter VI) suggests,
an adequate explanation of German political development wonki consist
of a set of curves over time describing environmental change and systemic
response. When these curves fluctuate or "kink" (in other words,
in crisis periods) we may assume that political resources and issues have
"opened up," [hat new coalition possibilities have emerged,
and that political leaders Iiave clioices which will effect tlie future
developmental path. Thus Rittberger suggests tliat a combination of time
series analyses plus a set of crisis case studies - including tlie Siein-Hardenberg
reforms in Prussia of 1807-19, tlie revolution of 1848-49, the constitutional
conflict in Prussia in 1862-66. and [he November (1918) revolution - would
give us a constellation of causes of German development which would "explain"
it more rigorously and definitively than is now possible. Simila*- research
strategies for British and Frencli development might begin to transform
the comparative political history of modern Europe into a more systematic
and reliable body of propositions.
We also argue tliat tin's approach to developmental explanation enhances
our capacity to predict developmental paths and outcomes. When we reacli
that point in the analysis at which we can specify coalition and policy
options, we are in a position to predict that the outcomes are narrowed
down to ;i specifmble and limited set of clioices with particular power
and policy propensities. This is a lot, but it is not prediction in any
precise sense. We have found in our case studies [hat we Iiave to predict
more than one possibly winning option, which in most cases leaves llic
actual outcome indeterminate.
|
|