|
|
Functionalism
and Systems Analysis
No two approaches have been more influential in contemporary comparative
politics than functionalism and systems analysis, and surely no others have
been more controversial. These approaches were systematically developed
in political science during the 1950s and 1960s, when the discipline was
shaken by the behavioral movement. Much of the terminology and conceptual
equipment that infused these approaches was new and different to the analysis
of comparative politics.
The Structural-Functional Approach
The use of Jargon in political science, or in the social sciences generally,
has been a source of deep frustration to tho^e-both inside and outside the
discipline-who seek to follow the literature. Jargon arises in response
to the need for precision in any field of knowledge. It provides, for the
initiated, shorthand notations for whole concepts or basic elements of a
scientific paradigm. If it is esoteric in excluding the layman. it nevertheless
seeks to provide precision in meaning for those within the discipline. The
purpose of jargon is more effective and efficient communication. The development
of jargon within a discipline may be a measure of its growth as a science.
The use of jargon, however, necessarily reduces the scope of communication
to those familiar with its specialized concepts and to those who share a
particular paradigm.
As has been frequently
noted, political science is pre-paradigmatic or is at least confronted
with a number of contending paradigms. In political science. Jargon, while
seeking precision, frequently only compounds confusion. In quest of rigor,
but lacking a scientific paradigm, social scientists do not always use
jargon in the same way, and, worse, some social scientists are not even
consistent in their own usage at different times. The issue of jargon
is especially germane to the conceptual frame-, works constructed about
structural-functional and systems analysis.
Perspective and Conceptual Framework
From its beginnings in the late nineteenth century, the functional approach
in the social sciences has been caught up in terminological confusion.
"Too often," Robert Merton has written, "a single term
has been used to symbolize different concepts, just as the same concept
has been symbolized by different terms. Clarity of analysis and adequacy
of communication are both victims of this frivolous use of words."'
The word function is used with a variety of meanings: occasion, use, aim,
consequence, activity, purpose, effect, motive, and so on. Its most precise
usage is in mathematics, "where it refers to a variable considered
in relation to one or more other variables in terms of which it may be
expressed or on the value of which its own value depends."2 In this
sense, for example, the rapidly expanding population of the developing
areas is primarily a function of declining death rates. From this notion,
the social sciences use the phrases "functional interdependence"
and "functional relations."
The origins of functionalism in the social sciences are linked most directly
to organicism and, specifically, to homeostatic physiology.3 The term
function, in this usage, is adapted from the biological sciences, where
it refers to the "vital or organic processes considered in the respects
in which they contribute to the maintenance of the organism."4
The premise of functional (or structural-functional) analysis "is
nothing less than to provide a consistent and integrated theory from which
can be derived explanatory hypotheses relevant to all aspects" of
a given social system. The approach is characterized by certain common
features: "first, an emphasis on the whole system as the unit of
analysis;
second, postulation of particular functions as requisite to the mainte-
nance of the whole system;
third, concern to demonstrate the functional interdependence of diverse
structures within the whole system-"5 The principal objective of
functional analysis is to determine the contribution which a social item
(a structure or process) makes to the persistence of the system in which
it occurs, that is, the role it plays in maintaining the system within
specified limits.
The logic of functional analysis, following Merton, involves the following
sequence of steps:
First of all, certain functional requirements of the organism [or the
social system] are established, requirements which must be satisfied if
the organism is to survive, or to operate with some degree of effectiveness-
Second, there is a concrete and detailed description of the arrangements
(structures and processes) through which these requirements are typically
met in 'normal' cases. Third, if some of the typical mechanisms for meeting
these requirements are destroyed, or are found to be functioning inadequately,
the observer is sensitized to the need for detecting compensating mechanisms
(if any) which fulfill the necessary function. Fourth, and implicit in
all that precedes, there is a detailed account of the structure for which
the functional requirements hold, as well as a detailed account of the
arrangements through which the function is fulfilled.8
Marion Levy states the problem of functional analysis in ordinary language:
What must be done if a society is to persist? How must what must be done
be done?7
While functionalism has been one of the dominant modes of analysis in
the social sciences, it has suffered continuous attack on charges that
it is "illogical, value-laden, and incapable of explaining anything."8
Functionalism has been criticized as verbally obscure; methodologically
ambiguous; teleological; conservative and ethnocentric; incapable of dealing
adequately with change; empirically untestable; and lacking in both explanatory
and predictive power.
Historically, writes Carl
Hempel. "functional analysis is a modification of teleological explanation,
i.e., of explanation not by reference to causes which 'bring about' the
event in question, but by reference to ends which determine its course."9
The final cause is presumed to determine the behavior of the system and
to "explain" a given social item. Here function closely approximates
purpose. This teleological perspective forms "the image of deliberate
purposive behavior or of systems working in accordance with a preconceived
design." There is no empirical criterion, however, for the attribution
of purpose, and to do so "tends to encourage the illusion that a
profound type of understanding is achieved."10
The roots of functional analysis are found in the work of Emile Durkheim,
but the British anthropologist Radcliffe-Brown made its formulation as
an approach explicit. The concept of social function is based, in his
words, "on an analogy between social life and organic life."11
It is, as Radcliffe-Brown well knew, a venerable analogy. It is also an
analogy which Chalmers Johnson has termed "uncritical."12
For RadcIiffe-Brown, individual human beings are "the essential units"
of analysis and are connected by networks of social relations into an
integrated whole. "The function of any recurrent activity ... is
the part it plays in the social life. as a whole and therefore the contribution
it makes to the maintenance of the structural continuity."13 Malinow-ski,
with his own variety of functionalism, shared this theoretical perspective.
He sought "the explanation of anthropological facts at all levels
of development by their function, by the part which they play within the
integral system of culture, by the manner in which they are related to
each other within the system. .. ."*4
"Chair-Tiers Johnson. Revolutionary Change (Boston: Little, Brown,
1966), p. 49. See also Robert A. Nisbet. "Reflections on a Metaphor."
in Social Change and History (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1969), pp. 240-304. There he writes, "Generalization
is beyond question what we seek from the empirical and concrete. But is
is generalization from the empirical, the concrete, and the historical;
not generalization achieved through their dismissal; not generalization
drawn from metaphor and analogy." (pp. 303-4.)
"A. R. RadcIiffe-Brown, "On the Concept of Function in Social
Science," American Anthropologist 37 (I935): 395-96, quoted in Merton.
Social Theory and Social Structure. p. 22.
"Bronislaw Malinowski, "Anthropology," Encyclopedia Brilannica,
First Supplementary Volume (London and New York: 1926). pp. 132-3. quoted
in Merton, Soda! Theory and Social Structure, p. 22. For a fine discussion
of the role that leading anthropologists have played in the development
of the functional approach, see Maurice Mandelbaum, "Funclionatism
in Social Anthropology," in Sidney Morgenbesser et al,. eds.. Philosophy.
Science, and Method (New York: Sl. Martin's Press, 1969), pp. 306-32.
The functional analysis
of RadcIiffe-Brown, Malinowski/ and other early anthropologists has been
described as "a dead horse" and of an extreme form which no
longer fairly characterizes contemporary functionalism.15 Robert Merton,
in his classic study of functional analysis, identifies three postulates
associated with classical functionalism:
first, that standardized social activities or cultural items are functional
for the entire social or cultural system; second, that al! such social
and cultural items fulfill sociological functions; and third, that these
are consequently indispensable.18
Merton argues, however, that these postulates are in fact unnecessary
to the functional orientation. Nevertheless, even the most sophisticated
functionalists remain vulnerable to the problems arising from these three
interconnected postulates.
The first postulate, that of the functional unity of society, is explicit
in the work of Radclirfe-Brown: "The function of a particular social
usage is the contribution it makes to the total social life as the functioning
of the total social system." This implies, he says, the "functional
unity" of the social system. Functional unity is defined as "a
condition in which all parts of the social system work together with a
sufficient degree of harmony or internal consistency, i.e., without producing
persistent conflicts which can neither be resolved nor regulated."17
In identifying "system-relevant" functions, few analysts specify
the reciprocal relations among these functions. Despite the assumption
that the functions are necessarily interrelated, the linkage is rarely
articulated. The degree of integration is an empirical variable and is
subject to verification- All societies are not equally well-integrated.
Changes may occur in the degree of integration within a society over time
as well as in the variation among different societies. Functions themselves
may also vary in relative significance for system maintenance both over
time and in different systems.18 Beyond this, the postu-
"Pierre L. Van den Berghe, "Dialectic and Functionalism: Toward
a Theoretical Synthesis," American Sociological Review 28 (October
1963): 695. Van den Berghe, En attempting a theoretical synthesis between
functionalism and dialectics, argues for the postulate of dynamic equilibrium
as "the real cornerstone" of the functional approach. He presents
"an expanded model of equilibrium" so as to allow for "the
possibility of maladjustive change, of vicious circles of malintegration,
and of abrupt 'social mutations' through revolution." (pp. 697-98.)
'^Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure, - p. 25.
"RadcIiffe-Brown, "On the Concept of Function." p. 397,
quoted in Merton. Social Theory and Social Structure, pp. 25-26.
"Robert T. Golembiewski, William A. Welsh, and William J, Grotty,
A Methodological Primer for Political Scienlisis (Chicago; Rand McNally,
1969). p, 253.
late of functional unity may divert the analyst's attention from the possible
disparate consequences of a particular social item for diverse groups
within the society or for individuals within these groups.19 In order
to deal with the multiple consequences any given item may have, Merton
distinguishes between functions and dysfunctions. Functions, for Merton,
are those "observed consequences which make for the adaptation or
adjustment of a given system." Dysfunctions are those which lessen
adaptation or adjustment.20
At any given instant, an item may have both functional and dysfunctional
consequences. It is always necessary to distinguish the object:
functional or dysfunctional in relation to what? What may be functional
for the society as a whole may be dysfunctional for subsystems within
the society. The unity of a total society cannot be taken as an assumption.
Functional analysis requires the specification of the units for which
a given social item is functional, and the analysis must allow for the
possibility of diverse consequences. A given social item may be either
functional or dysfunctional, or may be functional at one level and dysfunctional
at another.21
The second postulate, universal functionalism, holds that all standardized
social or cultural forms have positive functions.22 Malinowski states
this in its most extreme form; "The functional view of culture insists
... upon the principle that in every type of civilization, every custom,
material object, idea and belief fulfills some vital function.23 The basic
notion here is that whatever is is useful and serves some vital purpose
in the maintenance and integration of the social system-in short, that
it is functional.
A particular item, however, may be either functional or dysfunctional,
or, at the same time, have both functional and dysfunctional consequences.
As the same item may have multiple functions, all may not be intended,
or, for that matter, even known. Merton distinguishes between manifest
and latent functions- Manifest functions are those intended and recognized
by participants within the system- Latent func-
Funcfionalism and ^systems
analysis rations are those which are neither intended nor recognized-24
The concept of latent function sensitizes the analyst to the varied and
disparate consequences of a function and directs his attention toward
a range of consequences beyond the avowed "purpose" of a given
function.25 Marion Levy further distinguishes between those functions
which may be unintended but recognized and those intended but unrecognized.
"These concepts focus attention on the level of explicitness and
sensitivity of the members of a given system to the structures in terms
of which they operate."26
The third postulate, indispensability, follows directly from the second,
holding that whatever is is not merely functional, but also necessary.
Thus, Malinowski says that each cultural item, in fulfilling some vital
function, "represents an indispensable part within a working whole."27
A function is value-neutral. An item may be functional to the maintenance
of a system, but is not necessarily, in normative terms, good or preferred.
Preference is the product of a socially conditioned perspective. What
is functional to a repressive political system will surely not be valued
by the analyst merely because it is functional. The is, however, has all
too often been confused with the ought. The emphasis on system maintenance
and adaptation has carried a conservative bias, a justification and rationalization
of the status quo. This reflects, in part, the conservative origins of
sociology as a discipline, but the conservatism of functionalism lies
less in the nature of the approach itself than in its practitioners who
may endow the analytical model with normative value. Alexis de Tocqueville
warned against the confusion of the familiar with the necessary: "what
we call necessary institutions are often no more than institutions to
which we have grown accustomed."28
The functional model tends to stress continuity over change; at a certain
level, stability is assumed for analytic purposes.29 A model of society
in terms of integration and order may provide the criterion, in the form
of an ideal type, by which conflict and change may be exam-
ined,30 The analysis of
conflict and change as deviations from the '"norm" leads in
practice, however, to the frequent assumption that integration and order
are in fact normal and that whatever contributes to the maintenance of
a given system is not only functional/ but good.
Functional Inilispensabslity
Kenneth Sherrill31 has explored some of the problems of functional indispensability
in his analysis of Almond and Verba's The Civic Culture. Almond and Verba
posit the existence of" an ideal set of orientations toward politics,
or a political culture, which they term a "civic culture." This
culture is "mixed" in that it is characterized by a particular
combination of three citizenship orientations: the participant, the subject,
and the parochial. Each citizen is also characterized individually by
such a mixture.32 Almond and Verba select the United States and Great
Britain as "representing relatively successful experiments in democratic
government. An analysis of these two cases will tell us," they say,
"what kinds or attitudes are associated with stably functioning democratic
systems, the quantitative incidence of these attitudes, and their distribution
among different groups in the population."33
Not surprisingly, four hundred pages after deciding to use the United
States and Great Britain as their standards. Almond and Verba find that
these two nations most closely approximate what they have called the "civic
culture."34 This, of course, is considered the most desirable mixture
of people and orientations. From the assumption that the two nations are
successful stable democracies characterized by a cultural "mix"
at a particular time (the survey was conducted in 1959-1960), functional
value is then given to the peculiar character of the mix. If the United
States and Britain have a certain proportion of people with subject and
parochial orientations, that is, with low levels of political knowledge,
efficacy, and participation, then the maintenance of such patterns becomes
"necessary" for the stability and persistence of these
systems.35 In other words. Almond and Verba assume that the "civic
culture" is the only cultural mix consistent with democratic society,
when, in fact, all that they have shown is that the particular mix is
associated with those societies identified as most democratic.
Sherrill identifies another serious problem in the apparent assumption
that the three types of citizens-participants, subjects and parochials-
are randomly distributed within the population. The case studies of subjects
and parochials presented by Almond and Verba would suggest otherwise.
Deprivations are cumulative: Parochials tend to be disproportionately
poor, uneducated, rural, and, in the United States, black, Mexican-American,
and Appalachian white. "If maintaining the mix means maintaining
the pattern of life to be found in the rural south of the United States,"
Sherrill argues, "then the value of the mix must be weighed against
other, and perhaps higher, social values."36
In assuming universal and indispensable functional qualities for all aspects
of the system, Almond and Verba unwittingly rationalize poverty and social
injustice in the name of democratic stability. It appears that their norm
is stability, not democracy. In the concluding chapter, they argue that
if politics becomes intense, and if it remains intense because of some
salient issue, the inconsistency between attitude and behavior will become
unstable. But any relatively permanent resolution of the inconsistency
is likely to have unfortunate consequences. If behavior is brought into
line with attitudes, the amount of attempted control of elites by nonelites
will create governmental ineffectiveness and instability. On the other
hand, if attitudes change to match behavior, the resulting sense of impotence
and noninvolvement will have damaging consequences for the democratic
quality of the political system.37
This fear of mass political participation is also embedded in the pluralist
notion that apathy is functional to democratic stability. Empirical research
establishes that there are large portions of the populations of even the
most participant political systems, like the United States, which are
uninvolved, uninformed, and apathetic about politics. Such
"Sherrill notes, however, that "the question remains as to why
it is necessary to have certain people in the system who are subjects
or parochials, even though their ideal 'citizen' combines his participant
orientation with these other two orientations," "Political Modernization
as an Attitudinal Syndrome," p. 5.
"Ibid.. p, 6. Also seeSatish Arora, "Pre-Empled Future? Notes
on Theories of Political Development," Behavioral Sciences and Community
Development (India) 2 (September 1968): 111-15.
"Almond and Verba, The Civic Culture, p. 483.
apathy is the^ regarded as contributing to democratic stability by insuring
that political conflict involves neither large numbers of people nor those
who operate with an intensity unmediated by the "bargaining culture"
produced by the pluralistic pattern of crosscutting social cleavages.
In the b^st-selling introductory text. The Politics of American Democracy.
Irish and Prothro write, "Many people express undemocratic Principles
in response to questioning but are too apathetic to act on their undemocratic
opinions in concrete situations. And in most cases, fortunately for the
democratic system, those with the most undemocratic oprinciples are also
those who are least likely to act."38 "Too many good citizens,"
they contend, "could actually be bad for the system."39
The postulate of indispensability/ assuming that each element within a
system performs some vital function for system survival, goes far beyond
the minimum requirements of functional analysis. Merton argues, }\owevef^
that "there are certain functions which are indispensable in the
se"se that, unless they are performed, the society (or group OF individual)
will not persist."40 This is the concept of functional requisites,
those "imperatives" which must be fulfilled if the system is
to Persist. Closely related to the concept of functional requisites is
that of the functional prerequisites, those functions which must be fulfilled
or Pre-exist befo^ a given system can come into being. Despite the fact
lhat "embedded in every functional analysis is some conception, tacit
or expressed/ of the functional requirements of the system," Merton
observes that the functional requisite remains "one of the cloudiest
and empirically r^ost debatable concepts in functional theory."41
Levy insists that his requisites for the persistence of a society are
not derived merely by definition, but are the minimal implications of
the existence of ** society in its setting. They are not empty deductions,
but empirical relationships to be independently discovered. Talcott Parsons,
the most prominent functionalist in American sociology,42 argues, however,
that social scientists are not yet ready for a precise theoretical formulation
of social systems. This admits that the functional requisites on either
the general or particular level cannot then be determined.
Parsons "seems prepared to grant that functionalism is, at its best,
a programmatic guide to research,"43 For Parsons, functionalism is
a theory building strategy, a "theoretical device" for raising
significant questions and generating suggestive hypotheses. It is useful.
Parsons advises, to conceive of a social entity or process as a system
of behavior, having the teleological properties of self-regulation. Insofar
as this involves merely the view that the parts of society are interrelated
in patterns of behavior about which it is possible to formulate testable
hypotheses, then functionalism, as Kingsley Davis contends, is synonymous
with sociological analysis,44 Parsons and the proponents of the functional
approach, however, are clearly saying more than this.
Parsons, in his model of the social system, constructs an ideal type-He
posits four requisite functions, or "functional imperatives,"
for any system: (1) pattern maintenance, (2) goal attainment, (3) adaptation,
and (4) integration.45 "He is not making an empirical statement but
is proposing that it would be fruitful to categorize and interpret social
structures in terms of their contributions to these functions."46
But despite Parson's caution, he, as so many functionalists, fails to
preserve the distinction between the ideal type and empirical reality.
"In this way," Harold Kaplan writes, "Parsons' ideal type
is transformed into an allegedly accurate portrayal of observable systems,"4T
Flanigan and Fogelman argue that "there are no grounds for supposing
that one set and only one set of functions are requisite. The analyst
can define his 'requisite
functions' as he pleases, and he can be equally imaginative in locating
which structures perform what functions."48 This raises some severe
problems in the failure to distinguish empirical and normative criteria.
The analyst may well see as necessary those items which constitute for
him "good" system adjustment. "The danger is particularly
prominent because any 'requisite' is difficult to test, if indeed it does
not defy testing."43
The work of Gabriel Almond
involves what he calls "the functional approach to comparative politics."
As described by Almond in The Politics of Developing Areas, all political
systems have four characteristics in common and in terms of which they
may be compared. First of all, "political systems, including the
simplest ones, have political structure. .. . Second, the same functions
are performed in all political systems, even though these functions may
be performed with different frequencies, and by different kinds of structures.
... Third, all political structure, no matter how specialized, whether
it is found in primitive or in modern societies, is multifunctional....
Fourth, all political systems are mixed systems in the cultural sense.
There are no 'all-modern' cultures and structures, in the sense of rationality,
and no all-primitive ones, in the sense of traditionality."50 All
political systems, in this sense, are transitional.51
Although Almond nowhere offers a specific definition of function, he postulates
seven functional requisites which must be fulfilled by any political system.
On the political or "input" side are political socialization
and recruitment, interest articulation, interest aggregation, and political
communication. On the governmental or "output" side are rule-making,
rule-application, and rule-adjudication.53 The functions
are not of an equivalent nature, in that political communication is a
mechanism by which the other functions are performed-output, as well as
input, not to mention feedback.
"An adequate analysis of a political system must locate and characterize
all of these functions," Almond states, "and not simply those
functions performed by the specialized political structure."53 Nowhere,
however, does Almond make it clear just why these functions, and not others,
are necessary or whether they are sufficient for system maintenance. Almond
is deeply sensitive to the parochialism of traditional comparative politics.
His "functional categories" were developed for the purpose of
comparing whole political systems-Western and non-Western; modern, transitional,
and traditional. The functions, however, are highly ethnocentric in their
derivation. "The problem essentially was to ask a series of questions
based on the distinctive political activities existing in Western complex
systems- In other words, we derived our functional categories from the
political systems in which structural specialization and functional differentiation
have taken place to the greatest extent."54 This requisite assumption
provides the Pro-crustean bed to which all systems are fitted- The validity
of the assumption cannot be tested: "The same functions may be performed
with different frequencies, and by different kinds of structures."55
Thus, each of the seven functions must be fulfilled, by definition, if
the system is to be maintained. Since a given system to be analyzed obviously
"exists," then the functions are being performed. The problem
is to locate the structures, whether institutionalized or intermittent:
"If the functions are there, then the structures must be . . -"5S
The functions are offered as a "preliminary" proposal, "
and are modified in the development of Almond's work. In Comparative Politics:
A Developmental Approach. Almond and Powell distinguish between three
levels of functions, described as "activities."58 On one level
are capability functions (regulative, extractive, distributive, and responsive)
which determine the performance of the system in its environment. At the
second level, the conversion functions (interest articulation, interest
aggregation, and political communication; rule-making, rule-application,
and rule-adjudication) are internal to the system and involve the input-output
flow as the system meets demands with authoritative
decisions. The third level
is that of the system maintenance and adaptation functions, specifically
political socialization and recruitment. "The theory of the political
system will consist of the discovery of the relations between these different
levels of functioning-capabilities, conversion functions, and system maintenance
)nd adaptation functions-and of the relation of the functions at each
level."59
The broader framework is, in part, a response to the less dynamic character
of the earlier formulation. Almond seeks "to explore developmental
patterns, to explain how political systems change and why they change."60
His political system is one of interdependence, but not necessarily of
harmony. He offers a kind of "probabilistic functionalism,"81
but as the framework has expanded, the functional categories seem to have
become open-ended. There are presumably other, yet unspecified requisite
functions. Almond's use of the term function is hardly precise. but his
basic problem-the thorny issue of functional requisites-is shared with
Parsons, Levy, and all those who would employ functional analysis.
Political analysis has employed a diversity of requisite functions- "very
nearly a unique set for each study." Flanigan and Fogelman contend
that "until precise criteria are established for the identification
of functions and a theoretically sophisticated argument is made for a
particular set of functions," functionalism, as an approach, will
be severely limited.62
Closely associated with the identification of requisite functions is the
assertion that certain structures are "indispensable for fulfilling
each of these functions." Merton contends that the assumption of
structural requisites is not only contrary to fact, but diverts attention
from the possibility that alternative social structures may serve the
functions necessary for the persistence of the system. Functional needs
are permissive rather than determinant of special social structures: "just
as the same item may have multiple functions, so may the same function
be diversely fulfilled by alternative items. " Merton here seeks
to sensitize the analyst to the existence of functional alternatives,
equivalents, or substitutes.63
Different structures may serve the same requisite, and different requisites
may be fulfilled by the same structure. The relations between structures
and functions may vary not only between systems, but also over time within
a given system. The empirical determination as to
whether or not a given item has functional equivalents can be made only
under specified conditions. Hempel argues that "in most, if not all,
concrete cases it would be impossible to specify with any precision the
range of alternative behavior patterns, institutions, custom, or the tike
that would suffice to meet a given functional prerequisite or need. And
even if that range could be characterized, there is no satisfactory method
in sight for dividing it into some finite number of cases and assigning
a probability to each of these.""4
Carl Hempel argues that
"functional analysis no more enables us to predict than it enables
us to explain the occurrence of a particular one of the items by which
a given functional requirement can be met."65 From the postulation
of certain functional requisites, the inference is then made as a categorical
assertion that the requisites will be satisfied in some way. This assumes
self-regulation on the part of the system, that is, v/ithin certain limits
of tolerance or adaptability, the system will satisfy tt^e various functional
requirements for its persistence by developing the appropriate traits
so as to effectively meet any system challenge.66 In this sense, the system
is homeostatic. It is a teleologicaL or goal-directed system, and its
basic goal is self-maintenance.
Hempel points out, however, that "a formulation proposed as a hypothesis
of self-regulation can serve as a basis for explanation or prediction
only it it is a reasonably definite statement that permits of objective
empirical test. .. . Unfortunately, ... the formulations offered in the
context of concrete functional analyses quite often fall short of these
general standards." The kind of system or its limit of tolerance
within which the functional requirements are satisfied is not adequately
indicated.fi7 Ralf Dahrendorf argues that "instead of abstracting
a limited number of variables and postulating their relevance for explanation
of a particular problem, [functionalism] represents a huge and allegedly
all-embracing superstructure of concepts that do not describe, proposi-
tions that do not explain,
and models from which nothing follows."68
Part of the difficulty is that the key terms of functional analysis are
rarely given operational definitions and thus cannot be put to an objective
test.68 One of the most serious problems lies in the meaning of "maintenance,"
"persistence," or "survival." In biology, as Hempel
notes, "survival" of an organism has a fairly clear meaning,
but social systems are another matter altogether. There is always the
danger of tautology; Requisites are postulated upon which the survival
of the system depends, but as the system under analysis has obviously
"survived/' then it is assumed that the functional requisites are
fulfilled.70 In functional analysis, the definition of system requisites
must be supplemented by empirically testable specification of the "normal"
or "healthy" state of the system, with clear delineation of
the limits of tolerance beyond which the system can be regarded as no
longer persisting.71
The concept of integration, as noted earlier, is just as problematic as
that of survival. As all societies, over both time and space, will necessarily
vary in degree of integration, no society is likely to be perfectly integrated-including
those tribal societies from which the early anthropologists/ like Malinowski,
derived their vision of harmony.72 The concepts of adjustment and adaptation
involve similar problems of specification. In the absence of empirical
criteria, the concepts have no definite meaning. Tautologically, any system
response might be construed as an adjustment. Subjectively, adjustment
might become whatever the analyst regards as "good" for the
system in terms of his own values.73
The functional approach may account for the adaptive and modifying dimensions
ofi change/ but it cannot adequately confront radical and transforming
change. The functional vocabulary reflects in depth this bias, as can
be seen in the terminology of the "functional imperatives" of
Talcott Parsons- Words such as maintenance, adaptation, and integration
occur throughout the functionalist literature. As the challenge of modernization
unleashes forces of change throughout the world, the structural-functional
approach, at best, permits us to understand change only in terms of system
maintenance and preservation. Intrasystemic fluctuations are viewed in
the context of homeostasis and equilibrium.
Except in the case of genuinely
self-regulating systems, the explanatory power of functional analysis
is severely limited, and its predictive significance practically nil."
The task of functionalism in the social sciences is to determine the respects
and the degrees to which various systems are self-regulating. Failing
this, functionalism cannot be regarded as theory, Hempel contends, "but
rather as a program for research guided by certain heuristic maxims or
'working hypotheses.' "75
Functional analysis, as an analogy, provides an analytic and heuristic
model. It offers taxonomic frameworks and classificatory schemes for collecting
and coding research material. This was the conception behind the Little,
Brown Series in Comparative Politics. By following a common approach in
the analysis of individual countries, utilizing Almond's functional schema,
it then becomes possible to compare these countries "systematically
and cumulatively." Each country, rather than being treated in more
traditional, sui generis fashion, would be examined in terms of common
functional categories.76 Because "it provides a set of standardized
categories that can be applied successfully over widely disparate political
systems," functional analysis has been particularly useful in the
study of comparative political systems.77 It does not, however, provide
a body of theory, and it has neither explanatory nor
predictive power.
Systems Analysis
The systems approach in political science is closely related to functionalism,
both based on a conception of political phenomena as a "system of
interrelated and reciprocally regulated patterns of action and orientation,
patterns that cluster together in equilibrium and that . . . have certain
needs for maintenance and survival."78 Gabriel Almond, in his functional
approach, utilizes the concept of the political system instead of the
more traditional "state," limited by its legal and institutional
connotations.78 Almond distinguishes the political system in terms of
a particular set of interactional properties: comprehensiveness/ interdependence,
and existence of boundaries.80 In the work of David Easton, o however,
the systems approach is most fully articulated.
Easton, in The Political
System, published in 1953, offered a major critique of the condition of
political science as a discipline. In this deeply o influential book,
Easton argued for the use of the systems concept "as an analytical
tool designed to identify those integrally related aspects of concrete
social reality that can be called political."81 Over the succeeding
decade, the development of Easton's systems approach drew heavily on the
communications science of cybernetics and on general systems theory, an
ambitious attempt to provide an analytical framework for the study of
all phenomena, physical and social, as behaving systems.82
Easton wishes to construct an empirically oriented general theory of politics,
and to that end, he seeks to define the kinds of functions characteristic
of any political system through a systematic framework for political analysis.
He examines "the basic processes through which a political system,
regardless of its genetic or specific type, is able to
persist as a system of behavior in a world either of stability or of change."83
Easton's analysis rests on four premises;
1. System. It is useful to view political life as a system of behavior.
2. Environment. A system is distinguishable from the environment in which
it exists and open to influences from it.
3. Response. Variations in the structures and processes within a system
may usefully be interpreted as constructive or positive alternative efforts
by members of a system to regulate or cope with stress flowing from environmental
as well as internal sources.
4. Feedback. The capacity of a system to persist in the face of stress
is a function of the presence and nature of the information and other
influences that return to its actors and decision-makers.'4
As conceived by Easton, systems analysis
takes its departure from the notion of political life as a boundary-maintaining
set of interactions imbedded in and surrounded by other social systems
to the influence of which it is constantly exposed. As such, it is helpful
to interpret political phenomena as constituting an open system, one that
must cope with the problems generated by its exposure to influences from
these environmental systems. If a system of this kind is to persist through
time, it must obtain adequate feedback about its past performances, and
it must be able to take measures that regulate its future behavior. Regulation
may call for simple adaptation to a changing setting in the light of fixed
goals. But it may also include efforts to modify old goals or transform
them entirely. Simple adaptation may not be enough. To persist it may
be necessary for a system to have the capacity to transform its own internal
structure and processes.85 (see figure 5.)
The pattern of analysis involves the examination of the following variables:
first, the nature of the inputs;
second, the variable conditions under which they will constitute a stressful
disturbance on the"system;
\ third, the environmental and systemic conditions that generate such
\ stressful conditions;
\ fourth, the typical ways in which systems have sought to
cope with stress; o
' fifth, the role of information feedback; and, finally, sixth, the part
that outputs play in these conversion and coping processes.a>-
Easton emphasizes the analytic character of systems: "all systems
are \ constructs of the mind.""7 What constitutes a system is
determined by definition and is not given in nature. Nothing is gained
theoretically by designating some systems as "natural," for
the point at which a system of interrelated variables ceases to be a system
and emerges as only a random collection remains indeterminant.68 All systems
involve variables which are, more or less, interrelated. Easton suggests
that "any set of variables selected for description and explanation
may be considered a system of behavior." The problem is "to
decide whether the set of activities is an interesting one" insofar
as it is relevant and advances our theoretical understanding. The criteria
for the determination of what is to be included within the political system
is purely instrumental. "Logically, therefore, we are free to include
within a political system any { range of actions at all; substantively,
in the light of the objectives of ^ research with regard to political
life, we are limited by our conception -3 of what is significant and relevant
for an understanding of why people y> act in the way that they do in
political situations."89
Political systems are analytical constructs in yet another way. They involve
an abstraction of the political from the reality of the larger
matrix of human behavior.
The political system is made up of roles, not of individuals, and is defined
in terms of the political aspects of social action. It cannot be concretely
separated. Any action may be at once both political and non-political
in various aspects. Prayer would seem to be a solely religious act, but
when it occurs in a public school, it enters the political system. Voting,
on the other hand, is a political act, yet it may have specifically non-political
aspects, as, for example, in a case where voting reflects a desire for
social acceptance rather than political preference. Thus, in this sense,
the political system is not a physical entity, but it is, as a pattern
of interaction, empirically observable.80
Offering these caveats, Easton himself then breathes life into his political
system in such a way as to endow it with teleological character. It is
"a goal-setting, self-transforming, and creatively adaptive system."91
The analytic construct takes on a certain concreteness. Easton speaks
of the "life processes of political systems"92 and argues that
"the primary goal of political analysis is to understand how political
systems manage to persist through time."93 He gives little attention
to their transformation or "death."
Easton assumes that "there are certain basic political activities
and processes characteristic of all political systems even though the
structural forms through which they manifest themselves may and do vary
considerably in each place and each age."91 The requisite function
of any political system, and the criteria by which its boundaries are
defined. is "the authoritative allocation of values for a society,"95
that is, the process of how binding decisions are made and implemented
for a society. Values refer to those things, material goods or symbolic
re-\ A wards, which people want. They are, by definition, scarce. Allocations
| are those decisions and related activities that distribute, grant, or
deny ( values in the society. Allocations are authoritative when decisions
are o accepted as legitimate and binding, for whatever reason-threat of
force, self-interest, or recognition of legitimacy. The requirement that
.; such allocations be for a society distinguishes those decisions made
for . the inclusive social system from those in subsystems which may resolve
^ conflict through authoritative allocations of values, but for a limited
membership, as in a family, church, association, or local body of government.
The set of activities related to authoritative allocations for the society
as a whole Easton terms "the political system."
In all societies, scarcity leads to conflict and the demands for conflict
resolution. Where disputes over the allocation of values cannot be "resolved
independently and where they are also perceived to be excessively disruptive
of the prevailing ideas of order and justice/ every society provides for
processes through which special structures either aid in achieving some
regulation of the differences or impose a settlement."98 Insofar
as the authority is regarded as legitimate, the imposed settlement, ultimately
backed by the threat of physical coercion, will be accepted as binding
by most members of the society, even by those who may be adversely affected
by the decision.91
The boundaries of the political system are determined by whether the interactions
are predominantly oriented toward the authoritative allocation of values
for a society. What remains outside the political system constitutes the
environment, to which the political system is open and responsive- The
elements of the differentiated environment-the ecological, biological,
personality, and social systems-are taken as "given" and represent
the independent variables or parameters of the political system.98
Changes in the environment
relevant to the political system are conceptualized by Easton as inputs,
summary variables of demands and support. Demands represent the politicization
of raw wants or preferences. As these preferences are articulated, they
are "put into" the political system as demands that the authorities
respond to these self-conscious needs, that the government do something.
The volume and variety of demands are regulated by certain structures-interest
groups, parties, opinion leaders, or the mass media-which aggregate and
articulate the often diffuse and undifferentiated demands made on authorities-
By drawing the disparate variety of demands together in a workable and
simplified program for action, the system can presumably respond more
. effectively. Beyond these structural regulators, many cultural restraints
serve to modify potential demands arising from the environment. While
the sphere of every political system has increasingly expanded, certain
kinds of wants may still be regarded as inappropriate for political settlement."9
One of the most effective sources of demand regulation is in the differential
access which members may have to the political system. All members are
not likely to enjoy meaningful access and are not "equally likely
to give voice to a demand."100 The members of a political system
will differ widely in their political capital-money, status, prestige,
and numbers. With limited resources, the authorities of any political
system will respond most effectively to those demands from members with
political capital, upon whom they are ultimately dependent for support.
In this sense, the mode of analysis reflects an elitist orientation: emphasis
is almost entirely on politically relevant members of the system.101 The
model suggests a game of extortion, and, indeed, no political system operates
on solely altruistic lines. But Easton's model never really comes to terms
with what implicitly underlies the whole process. If ultimately authority
is backed by a "monopoly of the legitimate use of physical force,"102
all members of the political system are at least potentially equal. In
a Hobbesian sense, violence gives to each member political capital to
which the system must be responsive-either through repression or in meeting
the demands which may be expressed, as in a ghetto riot, by violence.
Three levels of support may be distinguished: the authorities, the regime
(or constitutional order), and the political community. Support for each
object may vary independently, but strong associative relationships normally
involve a "spillover" effect, by which support for one object
is transferred to the others. Political opposition is characterized f
as "negative support." Persistence depends on "the maintenance
of a minimum level of attachment for each of the three identified political
objects- Where the input of support falls below this minimum, the persistence
of any kind of system will be endangered."103 "A system may
seek to instill in its members a high level of diffuse support in order
that regardless of what happens the members will continue to be bound
to it by strong ties of loyalty and affection/' This form of support is
independent of specific rewards and is normally the product of a political
socialization stressing partriotism and loyalty to leaders, constitu-
tion, and country. "No system," Easton writes/ "could endure
for very long if it did not seek to build up a reservoir of support."10'1
Diffuse support may provide elasticity, but under what conditions does
such support "come to the rescue" of the system?105 In the long
run, every system falls back on specific support, generated by "the
satisfaction a member feels when he perceives his demands as having been
met."108 Outputs represent system response to existing or anticipated
demands and are distinguished from their consequences or outcomes. Authorities
may attempt to change the environment or to modify the political system
itself in seeking to fulfill demands. Alternatively, effective response
may be bypassed in favor of symbolic outputs-such as empty rhetoric, promises,
and flag-waving, or in the diversionary tactics of fear and scapegoatism.
This might be in the creation of fear of an external threat or of internal
subversion. Failing all else, authorities may fall back on the negative
output of coercion to ensure system persistence and their continued power.
No political system can meet all of the demands of all of its members
all of the time. The support by members serves as "credit" on
which the system operates, but "if the authorities are unable or
unwilling to meet the demands of the members in some determinable proportions,"
discontent would soon mount and system support, built up through previous
outputs, would decline.
Demands, independent of their impact or support, may impose stress on
the system in terms of sheer volume. It may be that there are simply too
many demands, with a variety, content, and intensity which overwhelm the
system in what Easton calls "input overload." No system has
an infinite capacity to accept and process demands, but the threshold
of capability varies with each kind of system, its structure and culture.'07
The capacity of a system to respond effectively to stress is derived from
the central process of feedback, information about the state of the system
and its environment, which is communicated back to the authorities, Feedback
is critical to system persistence, for "only on the basis of knowledge
about what has taken place or about the current state of affairs with
respect to demand and support would the authorities be able to respond
by adjusting, modifying, or correcting previous decisions, including the
failure to make a decision."108 Effective feedback, with maximum
accuracy and minimum delay, by
effective response. Output
failure may threaten any system- "Even if the authorities do obtain
accurate information, lack of will to use it, lack of resources to put
it to use, inadequate wisdom and skills in doing so may all contribute
as much to an inability to meet a decline in support as the absence of
such information feedback itself."109
Easton provides a model of "a vast conversion process" in which
"the inputs of demand and support are acted upon in such a way that
it is possible for the system to persist and to produce outputs meeting
the demands of at least some of the members and retaining the support
of most."110 The strains and imbalances which result from rising
demands and crumbling support are catalysts of system change.
Disturbances, both from the environment and from within the system itself,
may impose stress on the political system, threatening its capacity to
persist. The persistence of a given political system, Easton argues, requires
the presence of certain essential variables-"the allocation of values
for society and the relative frequency of compliance with them"111-which
operate within a "normal range." If these variables are displaced
beyond a critical range by stress, the system collapses. "Systems
analysis directs our attention toward the processes that all types of
political systems share and that make it possible for them to cope, however
successfully, with stresses that threaten to destroy the capacity of a
society to sustain any political system at all."112 It is by no means
clear, however, whether such system change involves radical / alteration
within a single, persisting system or whether it involves the creation
of an entirely new political system. The fact is that for alt Easton's
concern for systemic change, the processes of change-revolutionary or
evolutionary-are never fully discussed.
Non-persistence, for Easton, "suggests the complete breakdown and
evaporation of a political system."113 This may mean physical annihilation
or disintegrative anarchy. The disappearance of political systems may
be momentary-as a result of civil war, revolution, or military defeat.
While Easton says that a political system may recover its integrity, the
problem remains as to whether it is the same system. If the
political community, as
defined by geographic population, remains the same, perhaps the radical
change might be viewed as involving the system's persistence. The matter
would not be so-simple in the case of disintegration or amalgamation of
states/ as in the breakup of the Aus-tro-Hungarian Empire or of Pakistan
or in the creation of Malaysia or Yugoslavia. Even less clear analytically
is the situation posed by rival systems, as in South Vietnam, where two
governments claim control over the "hearts and minds" of the
people-one by day and one by night.
Persistence, in Easton's view, is more than self-maintenance, a concept
"heavily charged with the idea of stability."114 Persistence
demands resilience in the face of stress. If a system is to survive, it
must have the capacity to cope effectively with disturbances, either from
the environment or from within the system. The political system must be
able either to manipulate its environment so as to relieve stress or have
the capacity to make "substantial and significant changes" or
even fundamental modifications of its "scope, membership, structure
and processes, goals, or rules of behavior.""5 Thus, the system
is homeo-static or self-regulating, "even to the point of self-transformation/'118
Perhaps, as Eugene Miller suggests, "the remarkable capacity to persist
which Easton finds in political systems is due largely ... to his manner
of defining persistence."117
A Comparative Critique
Systems analysis, in its close relationship with structural-functional
analysis, is confronted by many of the same problems that plague func-tionalism.
Easton's model, for all his attempts otherwise, involves what Herbert
Spiro has called an "excessive preoccupation with stability."118
This need not necessarily be so- Morton Kaplan has argued that "if
we can construct a theory for a system or type of system, as a system
of equilibrium, we can then inquire how individual variations in the parameters
will produce deviant or unstable behavior."118 The view of
change or conflict as devianf
behavior, however usually involves a normative bias toward stability.
This is revealed in the very question Easton regards as the most fundamental;
how systems persist. Easton's concern with persistence and stress involves
a remarkable insensitivity to values, to the purpose of politics in terms
of who gets what. This lack of emphasis on distribution and goal attainment
is reflected in the discussion of roles, where, as Oran*Young points out,
"the flow of analysis is directed toward the contribution of various
role patterns to the persistence of the system, rather than toward the
contribution of the system to the well-being of the role holders."'20
In systems analysis, as in functional analysis, conflict is regarded as
a source of stress, a threat to system persistence.. Stability becomes
the highest value, the primary goal of system behavior, with political
consensus as its base. Beyond the conservatism the model may suggest,
serious analytical problems arise from the stability orientation. In emphasizing
"the functions of social conflict," Lewis Coser argues that
certain forms of conflict, rather than being necessarily dysfunctional.
may make important and vital contributions to the maintenance of the whole
system. In a series of propositions, distilled from the work of Georg
Simmel, Coser holds that conflict serves to establish and reinforce the
identity of groups within the system and that reciprocal antagonisms serve
to maintain the total system by establishing a balance between the various
groups and component parts of the system.121
However one may evaluate the utility of Easton's systems analysis, "the
simple fact of the matter is that this outlook has become a part of modern
political science."122 The concept of the political system is by
no means .new. Thomas Hobbes, in 1651, had written in those terms. "Anyone
who attempts to study politics scientifically," according to Herbert
Spiro, "must at least implicitly think of politics as though it were
functioning as some sort of system. That is, he must assume that more
or less regular relationships can be discerned among various aspects of
politics and between phenomena he describes as political and certain other
phenomena not so described."123
What Easton has done is to make these relationships explicit and self-conscious.
Easton provides a framework as a useful way of analyzing the political
world and of ordering the diffuse data of political life. It is a "conceptual
framework around which the more complex structure
Having analyzed separately
a number of theoretical approaches, it is now possible to assess the general
state of theory building in the study of comparative politics. A comparative
examination of the various approaches reveals a surprising similarity
in terms of stages of theoretical advance. Although certain approaches
may reflect slightly more progress in some arenas, they often lag behind
other approaches in quite different respects. No single approach therefore,
possesses a marked advantage in the overall process of theory construction.
of a theory may possibly, in the slowness of time, be added."124
In his aspiration to general theory, however, Easton has constructed a
model perhaps so ethereal that it is, lacking more explicit operationalization,
unlikely to yield empirically testable hypotheses and theories. As a consequence,
in contrast to the work of Gabriel Almond, it has had little direct influence
on empirical research in comparative politics. The deliberate degree of
abstraction frees the model from the specificity of any particular type
of system and thereby facilitates broad comparison, but it does so at
the expense of content.125 "The whole framework," writes Klonoski,
"has a sense of remoteness and abstraction from the facts and values
of politics." The gap between theory and reality is not effectively
bridged in such a way as to explain why things happen as they do.126
The structural elements of the system are never explicitly articulated,
and the "black box," representing the authority structures of
government-the traditional object of closest analytical concern-remains
shrouded in mystery. "While suggesting certain structural components
of a political system as a whole (the political community, the regime
and the authorities)," Easton does not provide the "concepts
needed to analyze the concrete subsystems of a system."127
The systems approach has sensitized the political analyst to the complex
interrelationships of political life with the whole social system of ^-which
it is itself a part. It has drawn attention to political phenomena as
constituting an interrelated system of behavior and, consequently, has
brought a renewed emphasis on the analysis of the whole political system,
as distinct from the study of its discrete parts or contributing elements.
Systems analysis, as in the case of functionalism, is most immediately
valuable, however, as a framework for classification and analysis of large
and diffuse aggregates of data.'28 By providing explicit and standardized
criteria by which political phenomena can be examined, genuine comparison
becomes possible. Herein lies the enormous contribution of both Gabriel
Almond and David Easton to the study of comparative politics. Whatever
weaknesses their schemata may entail, they have lifted comparative politics
from the intuitive and sui generis to a level of self-conscious theory
and systematic analysis.
|
|