|
|
The
Logic of Comparison
We have already argued in brief that the logic of comparative analysis is
dilTerent from the logic of other forms of social science research, especially
from tlic statistical method that tends to dominate social research. This
difference is evident in terms of the tendency of the unit of analysis for
statistical research to be the individual, as opposed to the collectivity
more commonly encountered in comparative researcli. It is seen more importantly
in terms of the manner in which (lie two methods deal with the crucial question
of controlling sources of extraneous variance. In the complex social world,
there are any number of factors associated with the variance observed in
any number of oilier variables. Finding signilicam statistical correlations
among those factors is rarelv a problem for social researchers. What is
more of a problem is determining whether those correlations are empirically
and theoretically meaningful; that is, can we say confidently that X causes
V, or whfiliei- they are merely the product of oilier, unmeasured, variables
affecting tlie variables actually measured. In other words, the real dillicultv
for the social sciences is making convincing statements about the causation
of political phenomena, given [lie complexity of interactions among the
whole range of social phenomena and llie number of external sources of variance.
Over a century and a half ago, John Stuart Mill (1846) was beginning to
grapple with some of the same issues, although he did not call it comparative
politics. Instead, lie was concerned with the fundamental logical and philosophical
problem of proving causation, an intellectual problem thai persists to tins
day (liialock, 1964; Aslicr, 19R'i; King et ill., 1994: ?:)-[ 14,). Many
social scientists remain very -sceptical about any claims of causation,
believing that the complexity ol the issues and (lie many interactions among
variables make claims
of causation suspect at
best. In his analysis of causation, Mill presented tliree conditions liiat
could be satislied in order to demonstrate a causal connection between
'variables':
(1) The Method of Agreement To paraphrase Mill, this method argues that,
if the several observations of the phenomenon under investigation (dependent
variable) have only one of several possible causal circumstances in common,
then the circumstance in which all the instances agree is the cause of
the phenomenon.
(2) The Method of Difference Again paraphrasing Mill, this is tlie argument
that, if there is an occurrence and a non-occurrence of a phenomenon (llic
dependent variable), and the circumstances in which these are observed
(independent variables) are (lie same in all circumstances save one, then
that one is the cause of tlie occurrence.
(3) The Method of Concomitant Variation If two variables tend to vary
in the same pattern, then they are somehow linked, either causally or
through some other pattern of connection (linked to some third variable).
These tliree methods for coping with the problem of causation were devised
long before contemporary social science, and indeed Mill did not consider
that his methods were appropriate for the social sciences. He (like many
scholars now) believed tliac tlie complexity of the causal relationships
encountered in social enquiry limited tlie possibility of discovering
meaningful causal relations. Despite Mill's own cautions, his three approaches
[o solving (lie problem of causation will be echoed rather strongly in
some of the researcli methods discussed later in the book (see Chapter
9), as well as in the discussion of fundamental problems of comparative
analysts in this chapter.
The basic problem for Mill, as well as for tlie contemporary social researcher,
is to isolate, as far as possible, a factor or a limited number of factors
that appear to produce (or at least arc strongly associated wnli) changes
in the dependent variable. This problem is, in turn, a problem ofidciilifving
possible ways to exclude the numerous possible confounding factors in
llie relationship between variables a problem of llie greatest theoretical
importance. The identification of tlie confounding influences is also
in part a function of having adequate theoretical guidance about where
to look for llic oilier variables (see Chapter 5). There are any number
of possible causes for changes in
political conditions - ihe secret is to use theory to identify llic most
likely sources of confounding variance.
Comparative Research Design
A more contemporary approach to the same problem addressed by Mill can
be expressed in terms of the variance observed in the dependent variable
in comparative research. Tlie fundamental litany for social research,
which will keep appearing in the course of this volume, is:
Maximise experimental variance, minimise error variance, and control extraneous
variance.
This is a relatively easy phrase to repeat, but a substantially more difficult
task to implement in comparative research designs. In each dependent variable
that we utilise for comparative analysis, there is always some of each
of these three types of variance - llic question is how much. Empirically,
it may be impossible to parcel out variance into these three categories.
This impossibility is true, because of (he numerous possible sources of
extraneous variance, and the numerous sources of error in any measurement,
and the associated difficulty in knowing when any particular observation
is aneclcd by error. Despite tlie impossibility of knowing how to attribute
all the observed variance, the researcher must still examine his or lier
methods with this basic question of research design in mind.
Expci imental variance is the observed diHi-reilces or changes in the
dependent variable that arc a function of ilie independent variables identified
as central to the analysis. For social-scientific analysis, even research
of a qualitative nature, llierc must be a dependent variable -something
\ve are attempting to explain. In some research situations, tlic dependent
variable may be a simple dichotomy - revolutions occur or they do not
fWickham-Crowlev, 1991), or people vole or they do not (Butler r/ ai.,
1981). In oilier cases, the dependent variable ni;iy lie a range ol responses
of governments to changing economic fortunes ((.oiirevilch, 1986). In
otiier.s. it may be a con-[inuou'i variable, such as per capita expenditures
for social welfare in a range of rouiuries (Hicks and -Swank, ty92; Castles
and Mitchell,
1993) that appears much
more like what we usually think of as a variable. For qualitative case
studies, the dependent variable may be changes in observed configurations
uf political power, or tlic nature of the decisions taken by political
elites, with those ditlerenccs often being very subtle.
Whatever (lie nature of variable in llie research, tlic investigator is
attempting to ensure lliat two characteristics exist for tliat dependent
variable. One is to be certain that it docs vary. Some published political
science research does not, in fact, utilise a dependent variable tliat
varies - at least in tlic data collected for [lie purposes of the particular
research. For example, a number of tlic recent studies ofdcniocratisation
have examined only those cases tliat have democratised successfully, however
that success is defined (Bova, 199]}. There is always (lie assumption
tliat (lie oilier end of the continuum was diucrcnl, but tliat assumption
was not really tested, ll may be that the variables used to 'explain'
successful democralisation may actually have roughly tlie same values
for those countries tliat did not democratise successfully.
This practice of selecting cases on llieir values on tlie dependent variable
has been argued to be one of the mortal sins that can afflict comparative
research (King el at., 1994), but tike most sins it is one which is practised
frequently. It appears to make sense to examine cases that satisfy some
criterion of relevance, but in fact this simply eliminates crucial variance
in tlie phenomenon to be explained, Even were relationships to be discovered
between successful dcmocratisa-tion and any presumed independent variables,
we would not know if they were any different from the relationships tliat
might be found for unsuccessful dcmoeratisations, or for authoritarian
regimes llial did not attempt to democratise at all. These may simply
be features of systems tliat have been authoritarian at one particular
point in time. About the best result attainable using only cases with
the same value on (lie dependent variable is to demonstrate tliat some
independent variable appears to be a necessary condition for tlic occurrence
of the dependent variable (Most and Slarr, 1989: 49-51).
As well as varying, il is good to have dependent variables that vary a
lot. While this issue may itself be largely a part of tlie general question
of measurement (sec Chapter 4), il is also a question for research design
and case selection. If we waul to develop robust theoretical slalemenls
that arc meaningful across a range of different types of circumstances
(and we certainly do) then il is wise to begin the research willi lliat
wide arrav of cases. Researchers would like to
develop, for example, propositions that work not only for the wealthy
industrialised world but also for at least tlie newly industrializing
countries (NIC.S - Singapore, Soiilli Korea, Taiwan, and so on), and iT
possible (hi- the less developed countries as well- Attempting to develop
theories with a wide range of applicability is difficult (see pp. 1 1
7-26), but we should begin with this as a goal, and therefore be concerned
in most research situations with selecting as wide a range of cases as
possible. The 'as possible1 in tliat sentence then raises the issue of
the judgment of the researcher, and [lie existing knowledge about variance
within the research environment. In the end, there may be no realistic
substitute for a researcher's good judgment,
Minimising error variance is less of a problem for case selection. Error
variance is that portion of the variance observed in the dependent variable
that is a function of random occurrences and errors in measurement. It
is the slip of the pen of the data recorder, or by tile data entry technician,
or sloppy fieldwork on the part of an interviewer, or a host of other
occurrences that can produce data points that arc just inaccurate. In
addition, no measurement of a social phenomenon is a perfect indicator
of that underlying characteristic, so a certain amount of measurement
error is almost inevitable. For qualitative research, this error variance
could result from faulty observations by the researcher, or the misinterpretation
of behaviours in different cultural settings, or jet lag, or again a whole
range of things that can produce inaccurate observations.
Statistically, error variance is assumed to have a mean of zero, since
it is random, and hence is assumed not to bias most statistical manipulations.
Tlic comparative researcher cannot anbrd to be so sanguine about the effects
of error. If the cases are selected inappropriately, or (lie observations
made bv the researcher are faulty, there is litlle or no way to recover
from the errors. Any results arising from research with such a poor design
and execution are likely to be misleading, and therefore in some ways
worse than no results at all. This potential for error simply argues for
even greater attention to the selection of cases, and a very searching
consideration of the comparisons ilial are planned at the beginning of
[he research, Further, there needs to be extremely careful weighing of
the modes of data collection to ensure thai they arc indeed compatible
in the range of societies within which they ;irc being applied, and that
the researcher is capable of doing the research in those countries.
Finally, there is tlic question of controlling extraneous variance. This
is even more a concern (or [lie comparative researcher, because
this is systematic rallier than random error. With extraneous variance,
there arc one or more variables that have a systematic relationship wilh
the dependent variable, and perhaps also with the independent variables
in an analysis. A researcher may find a relationship (statistically or
less quantitatively) between A" and T. The problem is that lliere
is a variable .<", that is systematically related to botli A'
and V. For example, we may find thai democratic political systems spend
more money on social welfare than do non-democratic regimes. The problem
is that levels of economic development tend to be related to both democracy
and welfare spending. Wealthier countries nnd it easier to maintain democracy
and also to spend money for social programmes. Thus, assuming tliat democracy
produces the welfare state may be only partially correct, if at all, but
that relationship should rather be tested in the presence of a measure
of the level of economic development.
In comparative research, there arc an almost infinite number of opportunities
for extraneous variance to creep into the analysis. Researchers tend to
be focusing upon whole countries or on large subnational governments,
all of which come as 'data bundles' containing a huge number of variables
and characteristics. John Stuart Mill referred to the nation as a 'permanent
cause', which no amount ol additional variables would permit one to eliminate.
When selecting a country for inclusion in a comparative investigation
the researcher will receive all of those factors at once- Attempting to
determine, therefore, whether the true 'cause' of the observed state of
the dependent variable was the independent variables or not is extremely
problematic. Statistically, at least, any variable lliat differentiates
cases at the level ol the country (or other geopolitical entity) is as
likely to cause the outcome as any other variable having the same effect.
In llie conduct of comparative political research, minimising anrl/or
detecting extraneous variance is a ditlicult problem, but not a totally
insurmountable one.
One o( tlie nrsi defences against extraneous variance is theory- As Faure
(1994: 313) points out, 'ocomparative method is therefore entirely dependent
upon pre-existing criteria ol relevance such as concepts, propositions
and llieories. These can be tested by the method but not discovered by
tlic method.' If lliere is good theory in the research area then it should
help the investigator determine whether the right control variables arc
being considered for a statistical analysis, or whether the appropriate
factors are being considered in .selecting llie cases in a more strictly
comparative
design. Faure may have
been too pessimistic given that, particularly willi statistical research,
finding inconsistent or unexpected results may lead to the search for
concepts that explain those findings, but, in general, researchers arc
dependent u]x>n existing conceptions ol'llie political world,
Tins reliance on theory may he a catch-22 for the research - if the theory
is already so good, why do we have to do the additional research? Further,
can tlie theory ever be really tested if we assume that its guidance in
the selection of cases and control variables is always reliable? Thus,
if the research in question is to remain within the 'normal science' mode
fKuhn, 1970), and assume tliat tlicrc is a reliable body of accepted and
verified evidence, then existing theory is a good guide. If the research
is more exploratory, or is intended to challenge the existing theories,
llien (lie researcher is more alone in tlic liostilc world of extraneous
variance. Again, the discovery or 'anomalies' (Kulin's word) may lead
to the questioning and tlien improvement of the theory.
A second possible defence against the problems of extraneous variance
is the use of time-series analysis, or using subnationa! units from within
a single country. Neither of these approaches to analysis is a perfect
prophylactic against extraneous variance, but each does provide some limited
protection. Using lime-series analysis will do two useful things in the
detection and potential elimination of extraneous variance- One is to
allow for the detection of systematic relationships other than those being
tested through the analysis. Suppose, for example, a researcher is using
time-series regression and finds a significant correlation between tlie
dependent and independent variables. That is very nice, but it is only
the beginning of the research exercise. There are a variety of'statislical
methods to lest whether tlic residuals (tlie difference between [lie actual
and the predicted values of each case) of the regression analysis arc
themselves systematically correlated across time. If there is significant
autocorrelation then this systematic error in tlic relationship can be
eliminated, cither through removing it by means of statistical manipulations,
or by identifying the variables causing the relationship and including
them directly in the analysis.
Examining residuals in this manner is most commonly done in time-series
analysis, but a similar logic could be used to identify systematic error
in other types of regression analysis- If [lie observations can be ordered
by any variable in addition lo those included in tlic analysis, ;ind if
tlic residual', are llien examined and are (bund to have a discernible
pallern, llien tlierc is an obvious danger of
extraneous variance contaminating [lie findings. For example, assume there
were ;> regression study of German lender that related per capita spending
on education to income. The results of that analysis would yield residual
errors, and these might be ordered by a potentially confounding factor,
for example, tlic percentage of Roman Catholics in llic population (Wilcnsky,
1974). Of course, a more useful statistical result could be achieved through
including the presumed confounding variable as a part of tlic regression
equation, and determining how it performs relative to others explanatory
variables. The virtue of examining tlic rc-siduals directly, however,
is that they may present a pattern lliat can be discerned visually quite
easily, but which would be more difficult to detect statistically. For
example, a curvilinear pattern might not be as easy to detect statistically
as witli a simple plot ol'residuals. Further, noting wlicre in the time-series
cliange in tlie autocorrelation-occurs may suggest the source of tlic
extraneous variance.
Using subnational units from within a single country also may lielp eliminate
some problems of extraneous variance. As has been argued above, these
units will tend to be more similar on a number of social and cultural
dimensions than will the countries in cross-national research. Therefore,
some of the potential sources of extraneous variance will have been eliminated
bv selection of that locus of research. Tlic problems witli this strategy
arc, among others, its relevance and tlic potential for a false sense
of security. First, many theoretical relationships in which a researcher
in comparative politics is interested will not be relevant in a subnational
context. For example, legitimacy is largely a question for national governments,
not for subnational governments, In many governments, however, subniitional
units as a group may have more legitimacy than the national government.
Tlie increasing disdain for (lie federal government in tlic United Slates
may reflect one notable case.
Also, assuming that tlie problem ofextrancous variance is solved by using
subnational units within a single country can lull the researcher into
a false sense of security. There are often still significant dilfer-cnce.s
among subnational units, even in countries that may appear to the casual
observer to be reasonably homogeneous politically, fur example, tlic differences
between Sicily and Lombai-dy in Italy. Therefore, extraneous relationships
may well lie present in subna-tiona] data without llie researcher being
as sensitive to them as lie or she might in a cross-national analysis,
and therefore unnecessary error can creep into the analysis.
Research Design and Case Selection
In the bcsl of all worlds, we might be able to do experimental research
to lest tlic propositions advanced in comparative politics. This is not
however ilie best of all worlds, and there are a huge number of practical
and ethical limitations on the capacity to expcrimciu on people and governments.
Therefore, we are led with attempting to find the best possible substitute
for the rigourous controls provided by [he experimental method. Tlie questions
of case selection and rescarcli design here are presented as the substitute
we have for not being able lo manipulate variables and randomise case
assignments. Any non-experimental design is subject to a number of threats
to validity (see below), and therefore political science researchers arc
in the position of merely attempting to do the best they can, given die
circumstances, 10 prevent contamination of their research findings,
The above solutions for die problem of controlling extraneous research
are ways of skirting the principal issue, which is how to cope with this
problem through the more direct means of research design and case selection.
We will talk about how many cases and the problem of small As in the following
chapter. Here, the principal question is not how many cases but which
ones, although these issues cannot be separated entirely, Again, if we
return to the fundamental differences between a comparative design and
a statistical design, for the comparative design we must deal with the
issues of controlling the sources of variance in the ex ante selection
of the cases, rather than through ex post manipulations ofdaia. Comparative
design tends to rely upon fewer cases, but ones tliat are selected purposefully
rather than at random.
The mosi basic question is, \Vhal makes cases comparable? (See Lijpharl,
1975b). It is difllcull lo attend any academic meeting on comparative
politics without hearing at least once (he phrase, 'But those cases really
are not comparable.' What does that statement mean, and what criteria
slioufd lie used for determining if political systems are indeed comparable?
Some social scientists (Kalleberg, 19G6) liave been enamoured of the criteria
assumed to apply in tlie natural sciences, and liave argued for very strict
standards of comparabilily. In tills view, cases could not compared adequately
unless they shared a substantial number of common properlics. This argument
was an attack on the siructural-fiinclionalisl'i, such as Gabriel Almond,
wlio sought lo include virtually all national cases
beneath their comparative
umbrella (Almond and Coleman, 1960;
Almond and Powell, 196G). Structural-functionalism used concepts that
were so broad tliat almost any political system could be compared, but
sceptics wondered if (hat truly was comparison, or simply putting essentially
incomparable cases into a common, and extremely nebulous, framework.
For the purposes of comparative politics, these criteria from the natural
sciences (if indeed they arc actually operative there) are almost certainly
too restrictive (DcFelice, 1980). First, we may well want to compare cases
that display a certain properly with those that do not. Wlial factors
appear to separate democratic from non-democratic political systems (I.ipsel,
1959; Prxcworski, i995a, b), or countries tliat experience revolutions
from (hose tliat do not (Wickham-Crowley, 1991)? Comparative politics
involves the development of theories explaining behaviour within groups
of countries that are essentially similar (see pp. 18-19). It is also
about contrasting cases that are different in any number of ways. Either
focus of comparison - explaining similarities or differences - can let)
tlie researcher a great deal about the way in which governments function.
Most Similar and Most Different Systems
One crucial question in the selection of cases has been advanced by Adam
Przeworski and Henry Teune (1970). This is (lie difference between most
similar and most different systems designs. The question here is how to
select [lie cases for comparative analysis, given that most comparative
work docs involve purposeful, rattier than random, selection of the cases.
Does one select cases tliat are apparently the most similar, or should
(lie researcher attempt to select cases tliat are the most different?
Further, like much of the other logic of comparative analysis, this logic
can be applied to both quantitative and qualitative work. Theda Skocpol
(1979: 40-1), for example, argued in essence for a most different systems
design in lier historical analysis of revolutions in France, Russia and
Cliina. These systems all generated major revolutions, albeit arising
within apparently very different political economic and social systems.
The question for Skocpol then
to explain relationships among variables in samples of individuals. Tlic
must different systems design is attempting to determine how robust any
relationship among [liese variables may be - docs it hold up in a large
number of varied places as if the observations were drawn frum (lie same
population of individuals? If it docs, then we have some greater confidence
thai there is a true relationship, not one produced by some unmeasured
tliird or fourih or fifth variables that exists in all relatively similar
systems.
Further, the basic logic of the most different systems is falsification,
very much in tlie tradition of Popperian philosophy of science (Popper,
1959). The basic argument is lliat science progresses by eliminating possible
causes for observed phenomena rather than by finding positive relationships.
As noted above, there is no shortage of positive correlations in tlie
social sciences; what there is sometimes a shortage of is research that
dismisses one or another plausible cause for tliat phenomenon. By setting
up tests in a wide range of settings, the most different systems design
attempts to do just that, while the most similar systems design can identify
many possible causes but can eliminate none- This problem can be seen
in part in a study of the Mediterranean democracies (Lijpliart el n!.,
1988). These systems were thought to be similar, yet once they were analysed
differences in their transitions to democracy did emerge. Unfortunately,
they were sunicicntly similar for it to be impossible to identify effectively
the root cause of those differences.
The logic of this approacli is therefore fundamentally different from
the most similar systems design. Whereas tlie most similar design dealt
with control through careful selection of matclicd cases, tins design
deals with [lie control issue by virtually ignoring it. In tlie most different
case, there may still lie unmeasured extraneous sources of variance, but
they will have to be very generic in order to survive in the range of
social settings in which the research may be conducted. This .strategy
is, however, also dangerous, given that it can create yet another false
sense of security in the strength of the findings. Indeed, the findings
may be gencralisable to a wide range of political and social systems,
but [lie underlying causal process assumed to exist may not, even though
it may appear from Berlin to Bombay to Bogota.
1 lie most similar ;>nd most different designs therefore do very dillcrem
things. Tlie former deals more directly with countries ;is a unit of analysis.
It allenipts to control for extraneous sources of variance by selecting
cases in which tlii-s is not likely to lie a major problem, although tlie
rese.m-her can rarely if ever know how big a
problem really docs exist. On tlie other hand, the most different design
is not particularly interested in countries; this is more variable-based
research, and is many ways closer to a statistical design than to llic
true comparative design. Tlie principal task in this design is to find
relationships among variables that can survive being transported across
a range of very different countries. Given tlie statistical nature of
tlie thinking here, controls for extraneous variance can be imposed
by the usual statistical techniques.
Tlie most similar and most dinerent research design strategies appear
very reasonable strategies in theory, but perhaps more difficult to implement
in practice. Giesele De Meur and Dirk Bcrg-Schlosser (1996) have demonstrated
more clearly how tlie approach to analysis could be used. They were interested
in the success or failure of democratic regimes during the post-war periods
in Europe. They first divided the countries into groups of similarity
based on the persistence or breakdown of democracy, and tlicn looked at
the most different countries in each group, based on distance measures
calculated from a large number of social and political variables- Thus,
they could look at "most different, similar outcome' cases to see
what variables were in common to explain these outcomes-
GtobaUsation and Gallon's Problem
A special case of tlie difficulties associated with controlling extraneous
variance in research design arises from the increasing gtobalisalion of
culture and politics. We can travel around tlie world and eat the same
food, drink tlie same soft drinks, and watch MTV or CNN (depending upon
taste) almost anywhere- We must also be concerned if lliere arc similar
globalising trends in politics, so that what we observe in one country
may not be llie result of any indigenous political process, but rather
may be a product ofdifiusion. Of course, tlie diffusion does not make
the occurrence of a phenomenon any less real, but it does influence any
analysis interested in developmental patlcrn'1, or tlie relationship between
economic and social conditions and political phenomena. For example, if
[lie familiar argument alxJLil llie relationship of economic development
and democraiisation (Lipset, 1959) is advanced, then any contemporary
findings may be i-ont.iniinated by tlie diffusion of democratic ideals
- forcibly through international organisations such as llie United Nations
and informally through the media and oilier social processes. This problem
may he furllier confounded by the differential receptivity of some
42 Comparative Politics
countries to diffused ideas, and tlic active scarcli by some for alternatives
to (licir existing policies and structures. Tlic Japanese, for example,
have been characterised as adept at borrowing constitutional ideas and
[lien adapting them to their own circumstances.
Globalis.Hion is simply a contemporary means of stating a very familiar
problem in llie social sciences, usually referred to as 'Gallon's problem'.
Tilis is tlic methodological problem ol sorting out diliusion from other
causes of variance in social systems. Gallon identified this problem in
relationship to similarities among cultures he observed in tlie work of
anthropologists, but it also arises in less exotic research situations.
There arc some cases iu which observed patterns of social behaviour simply
could not be the result of natural causes. 'Ibc prevalence of presidential
forms of government in Latin American countries throughout rcceni history
is a clear product of diffusion from the 'Colossus to the North' (Thibaut,
1993), rather than a natural process of institutional selection. Similarly,
the prevalence of Westminster-style systems in former British colonies
is a product of forced diffusion.
Oilier observed formats for government and public policy may be less obviously
a product ofdifTusion. Take, for example, tlie formation of social insurance
programmes in tlie countries of the world. \Vhilc tlic concept of social
insurance could be invented only once, the pattern by which it spread
appeared to follow a natural path of economic and social development rather
than one of more forcible diffusion. Several of [lie wealtliier countries
in Latin America, for example, adopted social security programmes long
before tlic United States or many countries in Europe (Mcsa-Lago, 1978;
1989). Did this pattern result from (he simple diffusion of ideas, or
were there socio-economic or political factors that made one group of
countries more fertile ground for these programmes than were others? Further,
even if there were diliusion involved, are societies and governments really
just tlic 'passive receivers of traits' (Smith and Craon, 1977:
145), or is diffusion dcpendeni in part on socio-economic conditions,
political traditions, or even cultural alTinitics thai facilitate diffusion?
Those conditions may mean that tlic society is particularly receptive
lo a programme that lias become 'an idea in good currency', or that there
may be a greater than average need for adopting the policy in question.
If tlie former is (lie case llieti (here is little to say, except to attempt
to understand diffusion processes belter (Rogers, 1995; Majonc, 1991;
Uolowity. and Marsh, 199G). If, on tlie other liand, there docs ;i|)pc;u
to be some systematic relationship of social and political factors to
(lie adoption of social insurance programmes then we may have fodder for
die tlicoretical mill on comparative public policy. The problem for research
design is to be able to sort out tlie possible causes of the observed
pattern as a way of addressing the theoretical question. For example,
we might begin by looking ai diffusion in specific linguistic or cultural
areas - do llicsc factors appear to make adoption of similar trails more
likely? Or do factors from a more political theory appear
David Klingman (1980) investigated
possible means of addressing
diffusion issues as they occur across botli time and space. The usual
comparative strategy is loo look only at cases at a single point in lime
and then infer a process, but Khngman wanted to demonstrate how to cope
(statistically at least) with sorting out effects of both temporal and
spatial diflusion. His argument is based upon the logic of autocorrelation
in regression analysis. As with patterning of residuals produced by systematic
relationships with a variable across time, patterning of residuals can
be a function of systematic unmeasured relationships across space, and
in this instance be a product of
diflusion.
Diffusion is a fact of political and social life, but it can confound
our
comprehension of causation in comparative analysis. It is all to easy
to assume that because attribute A' appears in country )' that it developed
autonomously. This is especially true if operating from an implicit or
explicit functionalist perspective in which any observed trait is presumed
to fulfil some function for the society. That need not be the case, and
some attributes may represent adoption of foreign traits and values virtually
as quasi-expcriments or to conform to perceived stereotypes of values
such as 'modernity' or 'democracy'. These political 'cargo culls' do show
something of tlic power of ideas in changing behaviour, but also can confuse
comparative analysis.
Levels of Analysis i
Another fundamental question for the design of comparative analysis is
how to link tlic individual and the collectivity. Comparative politics
t.s concerned about (lie behaviour of political systems, but it Es also
concerned about llie behaviour of the individuals within those systems
(Silverman, 1991). The problem is that it is very easy to slip Hiiu fallacious
reasoning that attributes tlic properties discovered at
compiiralive research,
studying a set of cultural attributes assumed to make democracy more or
less viable in ;\ country. It found thai several of tin-countries included
(West Oerm.my, Mexico and Italy)
one level ol'analysis l()
the otiier level (see p. lit). On the one hand, researchers (ire confronted
with the 'ecological fallacy', hi which the properties or a collectivity
arc assumed to characterise individuals within them. For example, in his
classic explication of the ecological fallacy, Robinson (1950) pointed
out that if we identify political units with higher rates of literacy
and then find tliat lliose same units have high rates of foreign-born
residents then it may not be that foreign born citizens are more literate
on average.
One more subtle version of tills fallacy, which is an all-to-common trap
for tlic comparative researcher in political science, is to assume that
something we call a country is a homogeneous unit, We know that the countries
in Africa that were carved out by colonial powers for their own purposes
are not homogeneous units ~ the outbreaks of ethnic warfare in Burundi
and Rwanda are unfortunate reminders of that. The lack of homogeneity
lends to be forgotten for more developed political systems in which variables
such as religion may cut across national boundaries. For example, Germany
may appear to lie a homogeneous country from outside, but the religious
cleavage remaining from the seventeenth centurv still influences the manner
in which politics and policy-making function in the two parts of the country
today. Other countries such as ttie Netherlands, Belgium and Switzerland
are divided by religion, language, or both (see Lane and Ersson, 1994a).
Furthermore, an entire country may be characterised as an outlier in some
distribution, because one part of it (geographically or socially) lias
very extreme values, while the remainder is quite 'normal', lying within
the distribution- For example, the United Stales lias a substantially
higher level of infant mortality than might be expected given its level
of economic development and expenditure for health care. If, however,
thai figure is disaggregated by race then the white population has an
infant mortality rate equivalent to that found in many European countries,
while the non-white population lias a mortality rate more similar to transitional
or Third World countries. Similarly, the slate of New Hampshire has an
infant mortality rate of 5.6 deaths per thousand live births, wliilc Mississippi
lias a rate of 1 1,3 - more than double that in the lowest stale.
On the other hand, researchers also can fall into the individualistic
fallacy in which tlie collectivity is assumed lo have the properties of
llie individuals that comprise il. Perhaps llic most important example
of tills fallacy would lie The (,'ivic Culture (Almond and Verba, 1967;
see Key '1'exl 2.1). This was one of tlic major pieces of behavioural
Key Text 2.1 Gabriel Almond and Sidney Verba, and the Civic
Culture
The Civic Culture has been widely praised and widely damned, but what
is certain is that this study has had a profound influence on comparative
politics. The study set out to identify the cultural characteristics that
made democracy successful in some countries and less successful in olhers.
In the end the argument was that a country such as the United Kingdom
with a mixture of participative and deferential components in its political
culture would be more successful than would countries that were more participative
(the United States) or more 'subject' oriented (Italy or
Mexico).
The Civic Culture was one of the first large-scale comparative surveys
conducted as comparative politics moved from its earlier institutional
focus to a more behavioral focus in conducting research. It was therefore
in some ways a model for the (then) newer approaches to the discipline,
and demonstrated the potential of mass political surveys as a research
tool for comparative politics. H also demonstrated the potential of linking
empirical research methods with normative questions (democratic performance)
in comparative analysis. Finally, the project developed several interesting
concepts about political attitudes and behavior that have
informed subsequent research in the field-
Although extremely influential in comparative politics, and the source
of numerous dissertations and secondary analyses, this project was also
roundly criticised. In the first place, although it purported to be objective
and 'scientific' there was a clear prescriptive element in the work, pointing
out what a good democracy was, and also what political development entailed.
Further, there were methodological questions about how to link individual
attitudes with the political culture of a country. Finally, The Civic
Culture apparently was not as careful about questions of the comparability
and meaning of political terms within different cultures as it might have
been, so that some of the findings are
suspect.
The above having been said, it is hard to diminish the importance of
The Civic Culture. It was a major source of encouragement lor comparative
political scientists who wanted to use the methods usually confined to
national elections or national public opinion polling. It also demonstrated
thai empirical comparison was really possible using those methods, even
given the problems that inevitably arose. did not have the attitudinal
support for democracy that others did, the inference being th;>t democracy
would not survive tlicre. Thus, ttie characteristics of the system as
a whole were being derived from the attributes if individuals - inaccurately
as it turns out.
Depending upon the purposes of tlic researcher, any level of analysis
will do well. The problem is simply not to mix the levels, or, if one
dues mix them, to pay careful attention to the possible misinterpretations
that may arise. Cross-level inference should be regarded as a crucial
question in comparative politics. As Heinz Eulau (1963: 47) argued, perhaps
the most important task in the discipline is:
to build, by patiently linking one unit to another, the total chain of
interrelationships which link individuals to other individuals, individual
to primary group, primary group to secondary group, secondary group to
secondary group, secondary group to organization, organization to organization,
and so on.
Ifsuch a sequence can be established then we will have a much better idea
of how politics works, whether at the individual, the group or the state
level-Further, this statement by Eulau points out that whenever we begin
an analysis we are cutting into a complex chain of causation. Simply focusing
on tlie individual voter, for example, may appear to be the right level
of analysis for understanding electoral behaviour, but we also know that
llici-c are important enecl-s of community and neighbourhood on voting.
Indeed, much of the analysis of voting behaviour lias depended upon class
as the explanatory variable (Nieuwbccrta, 1995). On the other hand, we
can obtain reasonably good ideas about how civil service systems behave
by looking at patterns of individual recruitment and the training and
ideas of the individual members of the service (Abcrbach el al., 1981;
Suleiman and Mcndras, 1995).
Threats lo Validity in J^on-Experimental Research
flie litany we have hccn discussing for coping with variance is another
way of expressing the problem of validity in social research. \ alidity
is the simple question ofwhellicr we are measuring wlial we think we arc
measuring, or whether (lie observations we make (especially on our dependent
variables) are a function of oilier factors not included in tlic analysis.
The 4'xpcrimental design charai irri.slic
Key Text 2.2 Phillipe Schmitter
and the Politics of Interest Intermediation
The study of interest groups during the 1950s and 1960s in comparative
politics was heavily nifluenced by American political science and its
pluralist assumptions. Although it was clear that in many countries interest
groups were organised very differently and played a different role in
politics, those differences were not adequately conceptualised. Phillipe
Schminer's 1974 article describing corporatism and positing different
types (stale and societal) of corporatism was a landmark in the understanding
of both interest-group politics and the politics of continental European
countries (see also Heilser. 1974).
Schmitter argued that rather than being the open universe of pressure
groups that was the heart of pluralist theory the consteallation of interest
groups in many countries was actually more tightly organised and restricted.
In particular, government played a central role in selecting the interest
groups with which they wished to interact in makign policy, tn this mode!,
a limited number of peak organisations would be granted direct access
to decision-making in exchange for some acquiescence to the decisions
once they are made.
This basic model of corporatism focussed on macro-economic policy through
tri-partile bargaining, although the corporatist notion appeared in principle
applicable to a broader range of issues.
The original Schmitter article spawned a number of extensions and elaborations
of the basic corporatist argument. For example, there were a number of
discussions of the boundary conditions for a corporalist system to exist
and why countries such as the United States and Japan had little or no
formalised corporatism. There was also a discussion of 'meso-corporatism'
for issues other than macro-economic policy . Similarly, the revival of
Rokkan's ideas about 'croporate pluralism' (see Key Text 3.1) in which
a large number of interest groups are granted direct access to policy-making
extended the concept of corporatism.
Despite the impact of the concept and the associated research there have
been a number of critiques. One of these has centered on the generalisability
of the concept; just as pluralism was used excessively. so loo has corporatism.
A similar critique is that the concept has been stretched to ocover situations
in which it is probably inappropriate. That stretching has been argued
to be true in bolh geographical and policy terms.
of tlie nalural sciences is supposed ti* solve ihosc problems lor those
disciplines, and some disciplines thai bridge tlie gap between social
and naluriil science for example, psychology. As already explained,
is
most social scientists
rarely have the luxury of conducting true experiments, and therefore must
find ways to make noil-experimental designs as valid as possible
When we speak of validity, \ve must be careful to separate two dlllerent
forms of (jig concept. One type is internal validity. This is llie capacity
to be sure [hat, if the independent and dependent variables
co-vary, then indeed the changes in A' did cause [lie observed changes
in /. T|^g question is a manifestation of the problem of extraneous variance,
which we have been talking about throughout much ol tins chapter. Internal
validity is generally not a problem for experimental research, since every
effort is made to liold as many laclois as possible constant through random
assignment, and the use of control groups permits checking whether that
cfTort has been successful. In "on-experimenlal research, however,
other mechanisms must be develop^ ^ cope with llie threats to internal
validity and the possible influence of extraneous factors on observed
findings.
External validity is a very different issue in research. It refers to
the question o( wilder any relationship observed among a set of variables
in the research setting is generalisable to the 'real world'. ror survey
research and statistical analysis, this amounts to whether or not the
investigator is justified in generalising from the sample to Ihe population,
\v\^ for strictly comparative analysis tlic issue is whether the cases
selected do reflect adequately the dimensions of dillcrcnt variables assumed
by the researcher. Experimental design actually performs very poorly for
this type of validity problem. The artthciality of the laboratory setting
for social research that provides it witli ihc ability to control extraneous
influences also divorces (hose findings from the social context within
which they have meaning. If
/- i i 'o "
\ve nnci mat people behave in a certain way in a psychological or
economic experiment can we have any confidence that they will
i i ' i
ueiuvc in the same way in their everyday lives? The answer is
probably not.
Internal versus p xternal validity is therefore yet another trade-on in
comparative research. Experimental designs are generally tlie gold standard
for internal validity, but are of little use for proving (lie external
validity of ^ finding. Indeed, many people would consider the hnclings
of laboratory experiments about important political issues to be mor<-
misleading than valuable. On tlic other hand, the type ol lesearcli more
common in political science tends to have a good deal of extern;i] validity
- it is based on observing the real world - hut can have a number of serious
deficiencies in internal validity.
The use of experiments
for many of the important questions of
political science may not he practical, so we are then left with attempting
to cope with the internal validity problems that arise from non-experimental
designs.
The obvious answer is to attempt to do both, and to test the findings
oftlie laboratory in a more natural setting, or to attempt to replicate
observed findings in a more controlled environment. One interesting example
of this strategy is the attempt to match experimental findings in international
relations theory witli real cases of foreign policy decision-making. Kaufmann
(1994) derived a series of propositions from rational and psychological
theories of foreign policy, then tested them by examining evidence in
the Imperial German archives. While such testing involves introducing
another potential source of error - the coding of the researcher - it
still constitutes an interesting way to address the internal and external
validity dilemma.
Sources of Invalidity
The principal approach to coping with the numerous threats to internal
validity in social research is to be cognizant of their existence, and
to use tliat knowledge to implement strategies to avoid as many pitfalls
as possible. When the pitfalls cannot be avoided entirely then conservative
interpretations of the findings can save the researcher and colleagues
most future difficulties. Donald Campbell and Julian Stanley (1967) havf
enumerated the.se potential problems in an extremely useful manner. Some
of (lie threats they mention have little relevance for most comparative
research, exerting their major influence on individual level research,
but some are endemic in comparative research. These should be discussed
at some greater length as means of arming die prospective researclier.
History
One very common tlircal to llie validity of comparative research i what
Campbell and Stanley refer to as history. This is the simple fact that,
while researchers arc observing a case and llie presumed interaction between
an independent and a dependent variable, there may be a number of other
changes going on around them tliat are impacting the observations being
made. l-'or example, any attempt to understand the p<ililii-;i! behaviour
oftr.ide unions in llie 1990s must take into .iccouiii the possibly confounding
enects of economic
Key Text 2.3 George Tsebelis
and Game Theory
In addition to institutional theory (see Key Texts 5.3 and 6.2), there
has been some growth in rational choice accounts ol comparative politics.
The assumption of this Iheoretical approach is thai the best way to understand
the behaviour of individuals in politics is to think of them as rational
utility maximisers, much as an economist would assume about their economic
activilies. In particular, Tsebelis applies concepts of game theory to
comparative politics, demonstrating that many common political problems
can be conceptualised as 'games' in which individual players choose strategies,
with the outcomes being determined by the structure of the payoffs available
and the strategies adopted by the competitors in the game.
Tsebelis was particularly interested in 'nested games', that is games
that occur are piayed within multiple arenas simultaneously. These games
often generate suboptimal outcomes even when the individual players are
acting rationally. As well as describing these games and their dynamics,
Tsebelis also points to their implications for institutional design. The
utility of the approach is illustrated with several examples drawn from
comparative politics, including consociationalism and coalition formation.
Rational choice analysis has a number of critics in political science.
The critics argue that political actors are not (necessarily) the rational
utility maximisers presented in these models but ralher operate from a
number of motives, personal utility being only one of many. Further, the
critics contend that these models oversimplify complex realities found
in politics, especially the behaviour of political institutions. The result
of that oversimplification is argued to be results that are either trivial
or misleading. Further, it is argued that rational choice approaches place
too much emphasis on individual actors and not enough on the role of collective
actors in politics, largely because of the problems of aggregating preferences
and rationalities in institutions.
Tsebelis acknowledges the criticisms and provides a vigorous defence tor
the approach. The defence may not be entirely convincing to the more committed
opponents of rational choice, but it will give even them reason to reflect
on their assumptions about politics. This book is a crucial slarting point
for anyone attempting to understand rational choice approaches in political
science and their applicability to comparative politics.
insecurity in a globalising economy. So, while trade unions may appear
much less activist lli.in in the past, thai may have nothing to do with
Factors suc-li as changes in leadership or changes in manage-
ment practices but a great
deal more lo do with the changes in the economy.
Observing a single case may make research particularly prone to the clFccts
of history, but using multiple cases may be no guaranteed way to avoid
the confounding effects ol'llial problem. For example, dillci-cnt countries
may react very din'crently to changing economic circumstances as a result
of historical experiences. There is some (Schmoldcrs, 1960) evidence,
for example, that the British public is extremely concerned about any
threat of imcmpioymciit, while the German public is mure concerned about
inflation. These concerns can be seen as a function of the economic histories
of (lie two countries. Britain was plagued by mass unemployment between
the two wars, while Germany suffered two massive inflations that wrecked
the economy. Younger generations may be less allccled by these fears,
but llicre is some sense that they do persist. Thus, a change in economic
variables would have a difTcrenlia) impact in these two systems [hat might
confound the findings of research attempting to assess the effects of
economics on political behaviour (Lewis-Beck, 1988; Andersen, 1995).
Selection Bias
We have been discussing the selection of cases in much of this chapter,
so that it may appear that there is little else to say on llie subject.
One point still to be mentioned, however, is that there is a natural bias
in comparative research arising from the tendency to select tlic cases
that the researcher knows best, and to attempt to make the theory fit
the cases rather than vice versa. Tins bias is very natural, and in some
ways logical, given that it prevents other types of errors of interpretation
and the barriers of foreign language to meaning research. The same logic
also creeps into the recruitment of multi-person research teams on dinercnl
countries, in which the tendency is always to 'round up the usual suspects',
lor example, researchers willi whom the organiser is familiar and who
have shown themselves to be reliable contributors in the past. A case
may be selected because of the availability of scholars rather than its
intrinsic merit. Again, that can be an antidote to otiier types of practical
problcm-s arising later in (lie research.
The above said, however, the preference for I'ainili.n- cases can present
severe problems in testing theory wilti the d.ua collected. The cases
with which we are most familiar arc nut necessarily llie best for testing
theories that are intended to have genera! applicability.
^
.6
Further, almost by dennition, ifwe want to think about theory testing
,o' through din'icull cases, ihen the less familiar countries and (lie
places s with perhaps die least welt-known scholars on the international
\i 'circuit' will probably be the most interesting. Comparative politics
r, is sometimes described by [is critics as the search for the most exotic
locales and for academic adventure, but in practice re-searchers sometimes
are wedded to (lie least exotic and the excessively familiar, and that
may be detrimental to theory development-In looking at instances of selection
bias in comparative analysis it is easy to assume that tills is a problem
for small-n, qualitative studies. Unfortunately, elegant quantitative
analysis can be used to mask some fundamental problems in case -selection.
All the analysis in the world, however, cannot make up for a 'sample'
that contains some systematic bias. Take, for example, Hahm elal.'a (1996)
study of fiscal policy. This study used a high selective sample of nine
countries to lest the influence of the nature of fiscal institutions on
deficits. That sample excluded Sweden and Norway, however, which have
quire similar administrative systems, but have had wildly different fiscal
policy fortunes in recent years- It also excluded Ireland, which has an
administrative system not dissimilar from thai of (lie United Kingdom,
but which again had liad very different policy outcomes. One can only
wonder at tlie utility of these findings. Similarly, much of the research
arguing for the negative impact of presidential ism on democratic stability
appears to be beset by some selection bias (see Power and Gasiorowski,
1997).
Instrument Kins
Instrument bias in comparative politics may be closely related to selection
bias, in that our selections are sometimes made on the basis of available
'instruments'. Tlie crucial instrument for comparative political analysis
is tlie individual scholar- That scholar may employ a variety of other
instruments, sucli ;is questionnaires or interview protocols, in Ins or
her work, but scholarly judgment and knowledge are the crucial factors.
The problem is that scholars all come with some built-in biases. These
biases may be theoretical, national or temperamental, among others, but
they will lie present. Further, given that comparative analysis is often
interpretative, those biases arc likely to influence the conclusions of
the work. Even if the research is quantitative, tlie selection of the
research question and tlie particular quantitative measures may lie influenced
by theoretic-ill and methodological biases dial exclude oilier possible
explanations.
One common strategy in
comparative research projects is to have one national expert write a chapter
on his or her country about what ever the issue at hand may be. This practice
often produces a published collection in which, as Christopher Hood once
commented, me major independent variable is llie author. Such a strategy
mav be especially problematic wlien tlie experls arc recruited from tlie
nations themselves, and therefore tend to replicate the prevailing national
analysis of llieir own system. In sncli a case, any implicit comparison
with other systems may be lost, and it is only the compiler of the volume
who can attempt to make any comparative sense out of the national studies.
Many editors have done tills successfully, but just as many appear to
have failed ratiier badly.
Maturation
As well as tlie external circumstances changing around a research site,
the internal circumstances can change as well. For example, take the case
of a scholar who is interested in decision-making in cabinets, and spends
time following tlie deliberations of a particular cabinet, even if from
afar, and through interviews with participants after tlie fad. Lei us
now assume that there is a reshuffle (a very frequent occurrence in parliamentary
governments ~ Italy lias had over 40 since 1945). In this case, the research
site has changed in a fundamental way, particularly if a key figure is
shuffled out, or a particularly eneclive new minister is shulllcd in.
Depending upon tlie particular focus of the research, tlie project could
well be ruined, and liave to start again wiili the new cabinet.
The change in a cabinet is a very visible change in the research site,
and that is probably fortunate. In that instance, the researcher can easily
notice that something lias happened in tlie research setting, and then
can make a decision as to whether- that change really impacts his or her
investigation. On tlie other hand, subtle and gradual changes in individuals
or organisations present a more dillicull collection of threats to the
external validity of findings, simply because they are. likely to occur
unnoticed- For example, after lenglliy bargaining over an amendment to
a piece of legislation, the legislators involved finally reach agreement.
Is this because the demands of all (lie participants wen; satisfied in
the linal proposals, or did they simply become tired? In sliort, individuals
and groups do change over lime, and those changes can anecl llic validity
of findings. The only real defence against thesf threats appears to be
awareness of the problems.
Regression Towards {he Mean
Another source of potentiiil invalidity in research is referred to ^ 'regression
towards llie mean*. This defect will result when (lie cascg for research
are selected on the basis of extreme values on l^
dependent variable. Given tlic errors inherent in any social measure.
incut, all subsequent tcsis arc likely to be less extreme. Further, givp^
the extreme values in tlie initial measurement, llicrc is nowhere else
for the observations to go, except back towards (lie mean, when there
lias been any en-or and extraneous variance in (lie initial measure. ment.
For example, suppose students arc selected Ibr an investigation on the
basis of poor scores on a test of educational skills, and are tlit-n given
a special class and then tested again. The second measurement is likely
to show that they have improved, and that tlie class was 3 success. This
observation could, however, be totally an artefact of regression towards
the mean, rather than revealing any real impact of the educational programme.
Sucli a source of invalidity represents a more individual-level version
of (tie problem in comparative politics of selecting cases on the dependent
variable. If we select cases of successful democratism. tion, for example,
then examine them across time, there is likely to bg a significant failure
rate of democracy. The 'sample' will, in essence have regressed towards
tlie mean of the distribution of democratic political behaviour in tlie
world. Thus, any 'treatment' we ai^ inferring from (lie environment of
these political systems - for example, changing economic fortunes or increased
ethnic- tensions-is suspect as a cause of tlie declining rate of democracy.
Similarly, the 'breakdown' of institutionalised party systems in democr;uic
countries (Dallon el nl., 19^-1; Lawson and Mcrld, 1988) may merely represent
a regression, of an aberrant form of parly system observed for only a
short period of time, towards the mean of parly systems in the generally
more fractious political world. We have cautioned against this practice
in a number of places in this volume, but the abov^ discussion provides
a somewhat more formal justification for those admonitions. We should,
however, also point ouE that selecting cas^s on (lie dependent variable
mav be acceptable and desirable as a means of generating hypotheses, just
not for testing them.
Regression towards tfie mean can occur wlien llic 'sample' used in tlic
research has been selected on tlic basis of its extreme values on the
dependent variable. While King et al. (1994), among others, liavc argued
against selecting on tlic basis of values on tlic dependent variable,
there arc some instances in which this praclice may lie
Key Text 2.4 Vincent Wright
and the Reform of the State
Most of Ihe attention on transformation ol political systems has been
directed toward the spread of democratic politics and markel economics
in the former Communist countries of Central and Eastern Europe (see Key
Text 7.1). To the West of those countries there also has been a major
process of transformation and reform, less dramatic but nonetheless significant.
This article, along with the others in the same special issue of West
European Politics (1994) describe and analyze those changes very welt.
A thorough reading of these articles will provide an enhanced understanding
of the intellectual debate over reform in West Europe and the other developed
democracies.
Vincent Wright and the other authors in this special edition demonstrated
that the state in Western Europe is becoming fundamentally different from
what it had been in the past- The numerous political and economic pressures
for reform have required some rethinking of jusl what government can and
should do in these countries. Further, the availability of ideas for changing
the State, especially the important of the market as an alternative to
the hierarchy of State bureaucracies, has facilitated the process of change.
Finally, the different policy challenges to government, many arising from
globalisation and Europeanisation. appear to require a different set of
structures and practices in order lor government to be effective.
What is perhaps most important in this discussion is that although these
states are changing in some important ways they remain in many ways unchanged.
The basic Ftechtstaat character of most European states is still in place
and, despite the numerous 'marketising' and other reforms bureaucracies
remain a central part of the apparatus for making and delivering services.
Further, despite privatisation of many public firms the State remains
a major socio-economic actor and continues to influence the economy in
many ways. These articles help the reader to see that despite (he change
government remains the principle source of guidance and control in most
Western countries.
acceptable or even desirable. Tlic regression argument makes it manifest
lhat one condition is clearly that iherc should be no inference based
on tlic retcsl of tlie same 'sample1, especially if tlial sample is extreme
in its values. This is rarely a problem for comparative politics, olher
than for some ci-oss-nalionat studies of public policies, in large part
because of the inability lo h;ivc a clearly defined mttTvenlion that would
makr a retest meaningful.
Conducting valid political research is never an easy task. There are a
large number of threats to th;it research lurking in practices [hat appear
normal, and even desirable (for example, looking only at cases that illustrate
a particular trait). Other threats 10 the validity of comparative researcli,
for example, maturation, occur as very normal parts of the political process,
hut still constitute significant threats to good researcli. Again, these
threats are almost inevitable in non-experimental research, so that the
major benefit to be gained from ibis description of [hose threats is simply
to be aware of [lie threats, in order to be able to discount their possible
impact on results, if not always avoid them. Thus, if a researcher knows
that a particular llircal to validity is present, and can estimate the
direction in which that threat is likely to have operated, then he or
she can make more conservative interpretations of the results.
Conclusion
Comparative political analysis is heavily dependent upon tlie cases selected
for analysis. This selection is often done in a haphazard maniier, or
on the basis of familiarity; as in Casablanca, we tend 10 round up [lie
usual suspects when starting on a project. Tliese may well be llie right
cases, but often they are not! Any project on European politics appears
to have to have [lie big [hree or four counlrics, although the smaller
ones are much more relevant theoretically. A researcher should lie able
to justify the choice of cases on theoretical grounds rattier than on
convenience grounds, but there are few consumer warning labels on comparative
research projects.
There are several views on how to select cases for analysis, the dominant
being (lie 'most similar' and the 'most different' systems design'1. These
two designs enable [lie researcher to examine different form of relationship
between independent and dependent variables, and therefore are suitable
for different types of enquiry. Again, however, one design or [he other
oflcn is selected on the basis of ease or familiarity with cases, rather
than through thinking about the nature of the type of comparative results
to be sought. Without attention to (lie projected outcomes of analysis,
the clioice of designs and of cases is unlikely to be (lie best one.
There is no single answer to all tliese questions. Although Prze-worski
and Tcunc (1970) liavc rather strong opinions about the best way to design
analysis, oilier scholars appear to have diametrically opposed views.
What appears to be most important is that the researcher consider his
or her options carefully before selecting a researcli design and (lie
cases that will he fitted into that design. It may be that llie purpose
of the research is not so much to find the cause of a particular phenomenon,
but rather is more exploratory, looking at an interesting phenomenon and
attempting to understand better something of its nature- In that case,
selecting 'most similar systems', and selecting on llie dependent variable,
might be a very reasonable thing to do. \Ve tend to focus attention on
llie uses of comparative research for theory testing and falsification,
and often forget that there are more exploratory uses that are equally
valid.
|
|